Menu
Home Explore People Places Arts History Plants & Animals Science Life & Culture Technology
On this page
Aristotle
Classical Greek philosopher and polymath, founder of the Peripatetic School

Aristotle was an Ancient Greek philosopher and polymath whose works span subjects like natural sciences, philosophy, and psychology. Born in Stagira, he studied at Plato’s Academy before tutoring Alexander the Great. Founder of the Peripatetic school in the Lyceum, Aristotle’s legacy shaped medieval scholarship, physics, and Christian theology. Revered as “The Philosopher,” his pioneering work in logic influenced scholars such as Thomas Aquinas and remains foundational in fields like ethics and science.

Life

In general, the details of Aristotle's life are not well-established. The biographies written in ancient times are often speculative and historians only agree on a few salient points.3 Aristotle was born in 384 BC4 in Stagira, Chalcidice,5 about 55 km (34 miles) east of modern-day Thessaloniki.67 He was the son of Nicomachus, the personal physician of King Amyntas of Macedon,8 and Phaestis, a woman with origins from Chalcis, Euboea.9 Nicomachus was said to have belonged to the medical guild of Asclepiadae and was likely responsible for Aristotle's early interest in biology and medicine.10 Ancient tradition held that Aristotle's family descended from the legendary physician Asclepius and his son Machaon.11 Both of Aristotle's parents died when he was still at a young age and Proxenus of Atarneus became his guardian.12 Although little information about Aristotle's childhood has survived, he probably spent some time in the Macedonian capital, making his first connections with the Macedonian monarchy.13

At the age of seventeen or eighteen, Aristotle moved to Athens to continue his education at Plato's Academy.14 He became distinguished as a researcher and lecturer, earning for himself the nickname "mind of the school" by his tutor Plato.15 In Athens, he probably experienced the Eleusinian Mysteries as he wrote when describing the sights one viewed at the Mysteries, "to experience is to learn" (παθεĩν μαθεĩν).16 Aristotle remained in Athens for nearly twenty years before leaving in 348/47 BC after Plato's death.17 The traditional story about his departure records that he was disappointed with the academy's direction after control passed to Plato's nephew Speusippus, although it is possible that the anti-Macedonian sentiments in Athens could have also influenced his decision.1819 Aristotle left with Xenocrates to Assos in Asia Minor, where he was invited by his former fellow student Hermias of Atarneus; he stayed there for a few years and left around the time of Hermias' death.20 While at Assos, Aristotle and his colleague Theophrastus did extensive research in botany and marine biology, which they later continued at the near-by island of Lesbos.21 During this time, Aristotle married Pythias, Hermias's adoptive daughter and niece, and had a daughter whom they also named Pythias.22

In 343/42 BC, Aristotle was invited to Pella by Philip II of Macedon to become the tutor to his thirteen-year-old son Alexander;23 a choice perhaps influenced by the relationship of Aristotle's family with the Macedonian dynasty.24 Aristotle taught Alexander at the private school of Mieza, in the gardens of the Nymphs, the royal estate near Pella.25 Alexander's education probably included a number of subjects, such as ethics and politics,26 as well as standard literary texts, like Euripides and Homer.27 It is likely that during Aristotle's time in the Macedonian court, other prominent nobles, like Ptolemy and Cassander, would have occasionally attended his lectures.28 Aristotle encouraged Alexander toward eastern conquest, and his own attitude towards Persia was strongly ethnocentric. In one famous example, he counsels Alexander to be "a leader to the Greeks and a despot to the barbarians".29 Alexander's education under the guardianship of Aristotle likely lasted for only a few years, as at around the age of sixteen he returned to Pella and was appointed regent of Macedon by his father Philip.30 During this time, Aristotle gifted Alexander an annotated copy of the Iliad, which is said to have become one of Alexander's most prized possessions.31 Scholars speculate that two of Aristotle's now lost works, On kingship and On behalf of the Colonies, were composed by the philosopher for the young prince.32 Aristotle returned to Athens for the second and final time a year after Philip II's assassination in 336 BC.33

As a metic, Aristotle could not own property in Athens and thus rented a building known as the Lyceum (named after the sacred grove of Apollo Lykeios), in which he established his own school.34 The building included a gymnasium and a colonnade (peripatos), from which the school acquired the name Peripatetic.35 Aristotle conducted courses and research at the school for the next twelve years. He often lectured small groups of distinguished students and, along with some of them, such as Theophrastus, Eudemus, and Aristoxenus, Aristotle built a large library which included manuscripts, maps, and museum objects.36 While in Athens, his wife Pythias died and Aristotle became involved with Herpyllis of Stagira. They had a son whom Aristotle named after his father, Nicomachus.37 This period in Athens, between 335 and 323 BC, is when Aristotle is believed to have composed many of his philosophical works.38 He wrote many dialogues, of which only fragments have survived. Those works that have survived are in treatise form and were not, for the most part, intended for widespread publication; they are generally thought to be lecture aids for his students. His most important treatises include Physics, Metaphysics, Nicomachean Ethics, Politics, On the Soul and Poetics. Aristotle studied and made significant contributions to "logic, metaphysics, mathematics, physics, biology, botany, ethics, politics, agriculture, medicine, dance, and theatre."39

While Alexander deeply admired Aristotle, near the end of his life, the two men became estranged having diverging opinions over issues, like the optimal administration of city-states, the treatment of conquered populations, such as the Persians, and philosophical questions, like the definition of braveness.40 A widespread speculation in antiquity suggested that Aristotle played a role in Alexander's death, but the only evidence of this is an unlikely claim made some six years after the death.41 Following Alexander's death, anti-Macedonian sentiment in Athens was rekindled. In 322 BC, Demophilus and Eurymedon the Hierophant reportedly denounced Aristotle for impiety,42 prompting him to flee to his mother's family estate in Chalcis, Euboea, at which occasion he was said to have stated "I will not allow the Athenians to sin twice against philosophy"43 – a reference to Athens's trial and execution of Socrates.44 He died in Chalcis, Euboea4546 of natural causes later that same year, having named his student Antipater as his chief executor and leaving a will in which he asked to be buried next to his wife.47 Aristotle left his works to Theophrastus, his successor as the head of the Lyceum, who in turn passed them down to Neleus of Scepsis in Asia Minor. There, the papers remained hidden for protection until they were purchased by the collector Apellicon. In the meantime, many copies of Aristotle's major works had already begun to circulate and be used in the Lyceum of Athens, Alexandria, and later in Rome.48

Theoretical philosophy

Logic

Main article: Term logic

Further information: Non-Aristotelian logic

With the Prior Analytics, Aristotle is credited with the earliest systematic study of logic,49 and his conception of it was the dominant form of Western logic until 19th-century advances in mathematical logic.50 Kant stated in the Critique of Pure Reason that with Aristotle, logic reached its completion.51

Organon

Main article: Organon

Most of Aristotle's work is probably not in its original form, because it was most likely edited by students and later lecturers. The logical works of Aristotle were compiled into a set of six books called the Organon around 40 BC by Andronicus of Rhodes or others among his followers.52 The books are:

  1. Categories
  2. On Interpretation
  3. Prior Analytics
  4. Posterior Analytics
  5. Topics
  6. On Sophistical Refutations

The order of the books (or the teachings from which they are composed) is not certain, but this list was derived from analysis of Aristotle's writings. It goes from the basics, the analysis of simple terms in the Categories, the analysis of propositions and their elementary relations in On Interpretation, to the study of more complex forms, namely, syllogisms and demonstration (in the Analytics)5354 and dialectics (in the Topics and Sophistical Refutations). The first three treatises form the core of the logical theory stricto sensu: the grammar of the language of logic and the correct rules of reasoning. The Rhetoric is not conventionally included, but it states that it relies on the Topics.55

Syllogism

One of Aristotle's types of syllogism56
In wordsIn terms57In equations58
    All men are mortal.    All Greeks are men. All Greeks are mortal.M a PS a MS a P

What is today called Aristotelian logic with its types of syllogism (methods of logical argument),59 Aristotle himself would have labelled "analytics". The term "logic" he reserved to mean dialectics.6061

Demonstration

Aristotle's Posterior Analytics contains his account of demonstration, or demonstrative knowledge, what would today be considered the study of epistemology rather than logic, but which for Aristotle is deeply connected with his account of syllogism.62 For Aristotle, knowledge is that which is necessarily the case, along with the study of causes.63

Metaphysics

Main article: Metaphysics (Aristotle)

The word "metaphysics" comes from the title of a collection of works by Aristotle bearing that title. However, Aristotle himself did not use that term himself, which is due to a later compiler, but instead called it "first philosophy" or theology.64 He distinguished this as "the study of being qua being" which, as opposed to other studies of being, such as mathematics and natural science, studies that which is eternal, unchanging, and immaterial.65 He wrote in his Metaphysics (1026a16):

If there were no other independent things besides the composite natural ones, the study of nature would be the primary kind of knowledge; but if there is some motionless independent thing, the knowledge of this precedes it and is first philosophy, and it is universal in just this way, because it is first. And it belongs to this sort of philosophy to study being as being, both what it is and what belongs to it just by virtue of being.66

Substance

Further information: Hylomorphism

Aristotle examines the concepts of substance (ousia) and essence (to ti ên einai, "the what it was to be") in his Metaphysics (Book VII), and he concludes that a particular substance is a combination of both matter and form, a philosophical theory called hylomorphism. In Book VIII, he distinguishes the matter of the substance as the substratum, or the stuff of which it is composed. For example, the matter of a house is the bricks, stones, timbers, etc., or whatever constitutes the potential house, while the form of the substance is the actual house, namely 'covering for bodies and chattels' or any other differentia that let us define something as a house. The formula that gives the components is the account of the matter, and the formula that gives the differentia is the account of the form.6768

Moderate realism

Main article: Aristotle's theory of universals

Like his teacher Plato, Aristotle's philosophy aims at the universal. Aristotle's ontology has the universal (katholou) exist in a lesser sense than particulars (kath' hekaston), things in the world, whereas for Plato the universal is a realer, separately existing form which particular things merely imitate. For Aristotle, universals still exist, but are only encountered when "instantiated" in a particular substance.69

In addition, Aristotle disagreed with Plato about the location of universals. Where Plato spoke of the forms as existing separately from the things that participate in them, Aristotle maintained that universals are multiply located. So, according to Aristotle, the form of apple exists within each apple, rather than in the world of the forms.7071

Potentiality and actuality

Concerning the nature of change (kinesis) and its causes, as he outlines in his Physics and On Generation and Corruption (319b–320a), he distinguishes coming-to-be (genesis, also translated as 'generation') from:

  1. growth and diminution, which is change in quantity;
  2. locomotion, which is change in space; and
  3. alteration, which is change in quality.

Coming-to-be is a change where the substrate of the thing that has undergone the change has itself changed. In that particular change he introduces the concept of potentiality (dynamis) and actuality (entelecheia) in association with the matter and the form. Referring to potentiality, this is what a thing is capable of doing or being acted upon if the conditions are right and it is not prevented by something else. For example, the seed of a plant in the soil is potentially (dynamei) a plant, and if it is not prevented by something, it will become a plant. Potentially, beings can either 'act' (poiein) or 'be acted upon' (paschein), which can be either innate or learned. For example, the eyes possess the potentiality of sight (innate – being acted upon), while the capability of playing the flute can be possessed by learning (exercise – acting). Actuality is the fulfilment of the end of the potentiality. Because the end (telos) is the principle of every change, and potentiality exists for the sake of the end, actuality, accordingly, is the end. Referring then to the previous example, it can be said that an actuality is when a plant does one of the activities that plants do.72

For that for the sake of which (to hou heneka) a thing is, is its principle, and the becoming is for the sake of the end; and the actuality is the end, and it is for the sake of this that the potentiality is acquired. For animals do not see in order that they may have sight, but they have sight that they may see.73

In summary, the matter used to make a house has potentiality to be a house and both the activity of building and the form of the final house are actualities, which is also a final cause or end. Then Aristotle proceeds and concludes that the actuality is prior to potentiality in formula, in time and in substantiality. With this definition of the particular substance (i.e., matter and form), Aristotle tries to solve the problem of the unity of the beings, for example, "what is it that makes a man one"? Since, according to Plato there are two Ideas: animal and biped, how then is man a unity? However, according to Aristotle, the potential being (matter) and the actual one (form) are one and the same.7475

Natural philosophy

Aristotle's "natural philosophy" spans a wide range of natural phenomena including those now covered by physics, biology and other natural sciences.76 In Aristotle's terminology, "natural philosophy" is a branch of philosophy examining the phenomena of the natural world, and includes fields that would be regarded today as physics, biology and other natural sciences. Aristotle's work encompassed virtually all facets of intellectual inquiry. Aristotle makes philosophy in the broad sense coextensive with reasoning, which he also would describe as "science". However, his use of the term science carries a different meaning than that covered by the term "scientific method". For Aristotle, "all science (dianoia) is either practical, poetical or theoretical" (Metaphysics 1025b25). His practical science includes ethics and politics; his poetical science means the study of fine arts including poetry; his theoretical science covers physics, mathematics and metaphysics.77

Physics

Main article: Aristotelian physics

Five elements

Main article: Classical element

In his On Generation and Corruption, Aristotle related each of the four elements proposed earlier by Empedocles, earth, water, air, and fire, to two of the four sensible qualities, hot, cold, wet, and dry. In the Empedoclean scheme, all matter was made of the four elements, in differing proportions. Aristotle's scheme added the heavenly aether, the divine substance of the heavenly spheres, stars and planets.78

Aristotle's elements79
ElementHot/ColdWet/DryMotionModern stateof matter
EarthColdDryDownSolid
WaterColdWetDownLiquid
AirHotWetUpGas
FireHotDryUpPlasma
Aether(divinesubstance)NoneCircular(in heavens)Vacuum

Motion

Further information: History of classical mechanics

Aristotle describes two kinds of motion: "violent" or "unnatural motion", such as that of a thrown stone, in the Physics (254b10), and "natural motion", such as of a falling object, in On the Heavens (300a20). In violent motion, as soon as the agent stops causing it, the motion stops also: in other words, the natural state of an object is to be at rest,8081 since Aristotle does not address friction.82 With this understanding, it can be observed that, as Aristotle stated, heavy objects (on the ground, say) require more force to make them move; and objects pushed with greater force move faster.8384 This would imply the equation85

F = m v {\displaystyle F=mv} ,

incorrect in modern physics.86

Natural motion depends on the element concerned: the aether naturally moves in a circle around the heavens,87 while the 4 Empedoclean elements move vertically up (like fire, as is observed) or down (like earth) towards their natural resting places.888990

In the Physics (215a25), Aristotle effectively states a quantitative law, that the speed, v, of a falling body is proportional (say, with constant c) to its weight, W, and inversely proportional to the density,91 ρ, of the fluid in which it is falling:;9293

v = c W ρ {\displaystyle v=c{\frac {W}{\rho }}}

Aristotle implies that in a vacuum the speed of fall would become infinite, and concludes from this apparent absurdity that a vacuum is not possible.9495 Opinions have varied on whether Aristotle intended to state quantitative laws. Henri Carteron held the "extreme view"96 that Aristotle's concept of force was basically qualitative,97 but other authors reject this.98

Archimedes corrected Aristotle's theory that bodies move towards their natural resting places; metal boats can float if they displace enough water; floating depends in Archimedes' scheme on the mass and volume of the object, not, as Aristotle thought, its elementary composition.99

Aristotle's writings on motion remained influential until the early modern period. John Philoponus (in late antiquity) and Galileo (in the early modern period) are said to have shown by experiment that Aristotle's claim that a heavier object falls faster than a lighter object is incorrect.100 A contrary opinion is given by Carlo Rovelli, who argues that Aristotle's physics of motion is correct within its domain of validity, that of objects in the Earth's gravitational field immersed in a fluid such as air. In this system, heavy bodies in steady fall indeed travel faster than light ones (whether friction is ignored, or not101), and they do fall more slowly in a denser medium.102103

Newton's "forced" motion corresponds to Aristotle's "violent" motion with its external agent, but Aristotle's assumption that the agent's effect stops immediately it stops acting (e.g., the ball leaves the thrower's hand) has awkward consequences: he has to suppose that surrounding fluid helps to push the ball along to make it continue to rise even though the hand is no longer acting on it, resulting in the Medieval theory of impetus.104

Four causes

Main article: Four causes

Aristotle distinguished between four different "causes"(Ancient Greek: αἰτία, aitia) or explanations for why an object exists or changes:105106

  • The material cause describes the material out of which something is composed. Thus the material cause of a wooden table is the wood it is made of.107
  • The formal cause is its form, i.e., the arrangement of that matter, the design of the table independent of the specific material it is made of.108
  • The efficient cause is "the primary source", the modern definition of "cause" as either the agent or agency of particular events or states of affairs. In the case of two dominoes, when the first is knocked over it causes the second to fall.109 In the case of an animal, this agency is a combination of how it develops from the egg, and how its body functions.110
  • The final cause (telos) is its purpose, the reason why it exists or is done, or function that something is supposed to serve.111 In the case of living things, it implies adaptation to a particular way of life.112

Optics

Aristotle was aware of Pythagorean optics.113 He used optics in his Meteorology, treating it as a science.114 He viewed optics as stating the laws of sight, thus combining what is now treated as physics and biology.115 The process of seeing involved the movement of a visible form from the thing seen through the air (or other medium) to the eye, where the form comes to rest. Aristotle does not analyse the nature of this movement; he does not anticipate geometrical optics.116

Chance and spontaneity

Further information: Accident (philosophy)

According to Aristotle, spontaneity and chance are causes of some things, distinguishable from other types of cause such as simple necessity. Chance as an incidental cause lies in the realm of accidental things, "from what is spontaneous". There is also more a specific kind of chance, which Aristotle names "luck", that only applies to people's moral choices.117118

Astronomy

Further information: History of astronomy

In astronomy, Aristotle refuted Democritus's claim that the Milky Way was made up of "those stars which are shaded by the earth from the sun's rays," pointing out partly correctly that if "the size of the sun is greater than that of the earth and the distance of the stars from the earth many times greater than that of the sun, then... the sun shines on all the stars and the earth screens none of them."119 He also wrote descriptions of comets, including the Great Comet of 371 BC.120

Geology and natural sciences

Further information: History of geology

Aristotle was one of the first people to record any geological observations. He stated that geological change was too slow to be observed in one person's lifetime.121122 The geologist Charles Lyell noted that Aristotle described such change, including "lakes that had dried up" and "deserts that had become watered by rivers", giving as examples the growth of the Nile delta since the time of Homer, and "the upheaving of one of the Aeolian islands, previous to a volcanic eruption."'123

Meteorologica lends its name to the modern study of meteorology, but its modern usage diverges from the content of Aristotle's ancient treatise on meteors. The ancient Greeks did use the term for a range of atmospheric phenomena, but also for earthquakes and volcanic eruptions. Aristotle proposed that the cause of earthquakes was a gas or vapor (anathymiaseis) that was trapped inside the earth and trying to escape, following other Greek authors Anaxagoras, Empedocles and Democritus.124

Aristotle also made many observations about the hydrologic cycle. For example, he made some of the earliest observations about desalination: he observed early – and correctly – that when seawater is heated, freshwater evaporates and that the oceans are then replenished by the cycle of rainfall and river runoff ("I have proved by experiment that salt water evaporated forms fresh and the vapor does not when it condenses condense into sea water again.")125

Biology

Main article: Aristotle's biology

Empirical research

Aristotle was the first person to study biology systematically,126 and biology forms a large part of his writings. He spent two years observing and describing the zoology of Lesbos and the surrounding seas, including in particular the Pyrrha lagoon in the centre of Lesbos.127128 His data in History of Animals, Generation of Animals, Movement of Animals, and Parts of Animals are from his own observations,129 statements by knowledgeable people such as beekeepers and fishermen, and accounts by travellers.130 His apparent emphasis on animals rather than plants is a historical accident: his works on botany have been lost, but two books on plants by his pupil Theophrastus have survived.131

Aristotle reports on sea-life from observation on Lesbos and the catches of fishermen. He describes the catfish, electric ray, and frogfish, as well as cephalopods such as the octopus and paper nautilus. His description of the hectocotyl arm of cephalopods, used in sexual reproduction, was widely disbelieved until the 19th century.132 He gives accurate descriptions of the four-chambered stomachs of ruminants,133 and of the ovoviviparous embryological development of the hound shark.134

He notes that an animal's structure is well matched to function so the heron has a long neck, long legs, and a sharp spear-like beak, whereas ducks have short legs and webbed feet.135 Darwin, too, noted such differences, but unlike Aristotle used the data to come to the theory of evolution.136 Aristotle's writings can seem to imply evolution, but Aristotle saw mutations or hybridizations as rare accidents, distinct from natural causes. He was thus critical of Empedocles's theory of a "survival of the fittest" origin of living things and their organs, and ridiculed the idea that accidents could lead to orderly results.137 In modern terms, he nowhere says that different species can have a common ancestor, that one kind can change into another, or that kinds can become extinct.138

Scientific style

Aristotle did not do experiments in the modern sense.139 He made observations, or at most investigative procedures like dissection.140 In Generation of Animals, he opens a fertilized hen's egg to see the embryo's heart beating inside.141142

Instead, he systematically gathered data, discovering patterns common to whole groups of animals, and inferring possible causal explanations from these.143144 This style is common in modern biology when large amounts of data become available in a new field, such as genomics. This sets out testable hypotheses and constructs a narrative explanation of what is observed. In this sense, Aristotle's biology is scientific.145

From his data, Aristotle inferred rules relating the life-history features of live-bearing tetrapods (terrestrial placental mammals) that he studied. He correctly predicted thatb rood size decreases with body mass; that lifespan increases with gestation period and with body mass, and that fecundity decreases with lifespan.146

Classification of living things

Further information: Scala naturae

Aristotle distinguished about 500 animal species,147148 arranging them in a nonreligious graded scale of perfection, with man at the top. The highest gave live birth to hot and wet creatures, the lowest laid cold, dry mineral-like eggs.149150 He grouped what a zoologist would call vertebrates as "animals with blood", and invertebrates as "animals without blood". Those with blood were divided into live-bearing (mammals), and egg-laying (birds, reptiles, fish). Those without blood were insects, crustacea and hard-shelled molluscs. He recognised that animals did not exactly fit onto a scale, and noted exceptions, such as that sharks had a placenta. To a biologist, the explanation is convergent evolution.151 Philosophers of science have concluded that Aristotle was not interested in taxonomy,152153 but zoologists think otherwise.154155156

Aristotle's Scala naturae (highest to lowest)
GroupExamples(given by Aristotle)BloodLegsSouls(Rational,Sensitive,Vegetative)Qualities(Hot–Cold,Wet–Dry)
ManManwith blood2 legsR, S, VHot, Wet
Live-bearing tetrapodsCat, harewith blood4 legsS, VHot, Wet
CetaceansDolphin, whalewith bloodnoneS, VHot, Wet
BirdsBee-eater, nightjarwith blood2 legsS, VHot, Wet, except Dry eggs
Egg-laying tetrapodsChameleon, crocodilewith blood4 legsS, VCold, Wet except scales, eggs
SnakesWater snake, Ottoman viperwith bloodnoneS, VCold, Wet except scales, eggs
Egg-laying fishesSea bass, parrotfishwith bloodnoneS, VCold, Wet, including eggs
(Among the egg-laying fishes):placental selachiansShark, skatewith bloodnoneS, VCold, Wet, but placenta like tetrapods
CrustaceansShrimp, crabwithoutmany legsS, VCold, Wet except shell
CephalopodsSquid, octopuswithouttentaclesS, VCold, Wet
Hard-shelled animalsCockle, trumpet snailwithoutnoneS, VCold, Dry (mineral shell)
Larva-bearing insectsAnt, cicadawithout6 legsS, VCold, Dry
Spontaneously generatingSponges, wormswithoutnoneS, VCold, Wet or Dry, from earth
PlantsFigwithoutnoneVCold, Dry
MineralsIronwithoutnonenoneCold, Dry

Psychology

Soul

Further information: On the Soul

Aristotle's psychology, in his treatise On the Soul (peri psychēs), posits three kinds of soul (psyches): the vegetative, sensitive, and rational. Humans have all three. The vegetative soul is concerned with growth and nourishment. The sensitive soul experiences sensations and movement. The uniquely human, rational soul receives forms of things and compares them using the nous (intellect) and logos (reason).157

For Aristotle, the soul is the form of a living being. Because all beings are composites of form and matter, the form of living beings is that which endows them with what is specific to living beings, e.g. the ability to initiate movement.158 In contrast to earlier philosophers, but in accordance with the Egyptians, he placed the rational soul in the heart.159 Aristotle distinguished sensation and thought, unlike previous philosophers except for Alcmaeon.160

In On the Soul, Aristotle criticizes Plato's theory of the soul and develops his own in response. Firstly he criticises Plato's Timaeus which holds the soul takes up space and can come into physical contact with bodies.161 20th-century scholarship held that Aristotle had here misinterpreted Plato.162 Aristotle also argued that Plato's view of reincarnation entails that a soul and its body can be mis-matched; in principle, Aristotle alleges, any soul can go with any body, according to Plato's theory.163

Memory

According to Aristotle in On the Soul, memory is the ability to hold a perceived experience in the mind and to distinguish between the internal "appearance" and a past occurrence.164 A memory is a mental picture (phantasm) that can be recovered. An impression is left on a semi-fluid bodily organ that undergoes changes in order to make a memory. A memory occurs when stimuli such as sights or sounds are so complex that the nervous system cannot receive them all at once. These changes are the same as those involved in sensation, 'common sense', and thinking.165166

Aristotle uses the term 'memory' for the actual retaining of an experience in the impression that develops from sensation, and for the intellectual anxiety that comes with the impression because it is formed at a particular time and processing specific contents. Memory is of the past, prediction is of the future, and sensation is of the present. Retrieval of impressions cannot be performed suddenly. A transitional channel is needed and located in past experiences, both for previous experience and present experience.167

Because Aristotle believes people perceive all kinds of sense perceptions as impressions, people continually weave together new impressions of experiences. To search for impressions, people search memory itself.168 Within memory, if an experience is offered instead of a specific memory, that person will reject this experience until they find what they are looking for. Recollection occurs when a retrieved experience naturally follows another. If the chain of "images" is needed, one memory stimulates the next. When people recall experiences, they stimulate certain previous experiences until they reach the one that is needed.169 Recollection is thus the self-directed activity of retrieving information stored in a memory impression.170 Only humans can remember impressions of intellectual activity, such as numbers and words. Animals that have perception of time can retrieve memories of their past observations. Remembering involves only perception of the things remembered and of the time passed.171

Aristotle believed the chain of thought that achieves recollection of impressions was connected systematically in relationships such as similarity, contrast, and contiguity, described in his laws of association. Aristotle believed that past experiences are hidden within the mind. A force operates to awaken the hidden material to bring up the actual experience. Association is the power innate in a mental state, which operates upon the unexpressed remains of former experiences, allowing them to be recalled.172173

Dreams

Further information: Dream § Other

Aristotle describes sleep in On Sleep and Wakefulness.174 It is a result of overuse of the senses175 or of digestion,176 and is vital to the body.177 While a person is asleep, the critical activities, which include thinking, sensing, recalling and remembering, do not function. Since a person cannot sense during sleep, they cannot have desire. However, the senses work during sleep,178 albeit differently.179

Dreams do not involve sensing a stimulus. Sensation is involved, but in an altered manner.180 Aristotle explains that when a person stares at a moving stimulus such as the waves in a body of water, and then looks away, the next thing they look at appears to have a wavelike motion. When a person perceives a stimulus and it is no longer the focus of their attention, it leaves an impression.181 When the body is awake, a person constantly encounters new stimuli and so the impressions of previous stimuli are ignored.182 However, during sleep the impressions made throughout the day are noticed, free of distractions.183 So, dreams result from these lasting impressions. Since impressions are all that are left, dreams do not resemble waking experience.184 During sleep, a person is in an altered state of mind, like a person who is overtaken by strong feelings. For example, a person who has a strong infatuation with someone may begin to think they see that person everywhere. Since a person sleeping is in a suggestible state and unable to make judgements, they become easily deceived by what appears in their dreams, like the infatuated person.185 This leads them to believe the dream is real, even when the dreams are absurd.186 In De Anima iii 3, Aristotle ascribes the ability to create, to store, and to recall images to the faculty of imagination, phantasia.187

One component of Aristotle's theory disagrees with previously held beliefs. He claimed that dreams are not foretelling and not sent by a divine being. Aristotle reasoned that instances in which dreams resemble future events are simply coincidences.188 Any sensory experience perceived while a person is asleep, such as actually hearing a door close, does not qualify as part of a dream. Images of dreams must be a result of lasting impressions of waking sensory experiences.189

Practical philosophy

Aristotle's practical philosophy covers areas such as ethics, politics, economics, and rhetoric.190

Virtues and their accompanying vices191
Too littleVirtuous meanToo much
HumblenessHigh-mindednessVainglory
Lack of purposeRight ambitionOver-ambition
SpiritlessnessGood temperIrascibility
RudenessCivilityObsequiousness
CowardiceCourageRashness
InsensibilitySelf-controlIntemperance
SarcasmSincerityBoastfulness
BoorishnessWitBuffoonery
CallousnessJust resentmentSpitefulness
PettinessGenerosityVulgarity
MeannessLiberalityWastefulness

Ethics

Main article: Aristotelian ethics

Aristotle was a virtue ethicist who considered ethics to be a practical rather than theoretical study, i.e., one aimed at becoming good and doing good rather than knowing for its own sake. He wrote several treatises on ethics, most notably including the Nicomachean Ethics.192

Aristotle taught that virtue has to do with the proper function (ergon) of a thing. An eye is only a good eye in so much as it can see because the proper function of an eye is sight. Aristotle reasoned that humans must have a function specific to humans, and that this function must be an activity of the psuchē (soul) in accordance with reason (logos). Aristotle identified such an optimum activity (the virtuous mean, between the accompanying vices of excess or deficiency193) of the soul as the aim of all human deliberate action, eudaimonia, generally translated as "happiness" or sometimes "well-being". To have the potential of ever being happy in this way necessarily requires a good character (ēthikē aretē), often translated as moral or ethical virtue or excellence.194

Aristotle taught that to achieve a virtuous and potentially happy character requires a first stage of having the fortune to be habituated, not deliberately, but by teachers, and experience, leading to a later stage in which one consciously chooses to do the best things, becoming the phronimos or virtuous man. When the best people come to live life this way their practical wisdom (phronesis) and their intellect (nous) can develop with each other towards the highest possible human virtue, the wisdom of an accomplished theoretical or speculative thinker, or in other words, a philosopher.195

Politics

Main article: Politics (Aristotle)

In addition to his works on ethics, which address the individual, Aristotle addressed the city in his work titled Politics. Aristotle considered the city to be a natural community. Moreover, he considered the city to be prior in importance to the family, which in turn is prior to the individual, "for the whole must of necessity be prior to the part".196 He famously stated that "man is by nature a political animal" and argued that humanity's defining factor among others in the animal kingdom is its rationality.197 Aristotle conceived of politics as being like an organism rather than like a machine, and as a collection of parts, none of which can exist without the others. Aristotle's conception of the city is organic, and he is considered one of the first to conceive of the city in this manner.198

The common modern understanding of a political community as a modern state is quite different from Aristotle's understanding. Although he was aware of the existence and potential of larger empires, the natural community according to Aristotle was the city (polis) which functions as a political "community" or "partnership" (koinōnia). The aim of the city is not just to avoid injustice or for economic stability, but rather to allow at least some citizens the possibility to live a good life, and to perform beautiful acts: "The political partnership must be regarded, therefore, as being for the sake of noble actions, not for the sake of living together." This is distinguished from modern approaches, beginning with social contract theory, according to which individuals leave the state of nature because of "fear of violent death" or its "inconveniences".199

In Protrepticus, the character 'Aristotle' states:200

For we all agree that the most excellent man should rule, i.e., the supreme by nature, and that the law rules and alone is authoritative; but the law is a kind of intelligence, i.e. a discourse based on intelligence. And again, what standard do we have, what criterion of good things, that is more precise than the intelligent man? For all that this man will choose, if the choice is based on his knowledge, are good things and their contraries are bad. And since everybody chooses most of all what conforms to their own proper dispositions (a just man choosing to live justly, a man with bravery to live bravely, likewise a self-controlled man to live with self-control), it is clear that the intelligent man will choose most of all to be intelligent; for this is the function of that capacity. Hence it's evident that, according to the most authoritative judgment, intelligence is supreme among goods.201

As Plato's disciple Aristotle was rather critical concerning democracy and, following the outline of certain ideas from Plato's Statesman, he developed a coherent theory of integrating various forms of power into a so-called mixed state:

It is ... constitutional to take ... from oligarchy that offices are to be elected, and from democracy that this is not to be on a property-qualification. This then is the mode of the mixture; and the mark of a good mixture of democracy and oligarchy is when it is possible to speak of the same constitution as a democracy and as an oligarchy.

— Aristotle. Politics, Book 4, 1294b.10–18

Economics

Main article: Politics (Aristotle)

Aristotle made substantial contributions to economic thought, especially to thought in the Middle Ages.202 In Politics, Aristotle addresses the city, property, and trade. His response to criticisms of private property, in Lionel Robbins's view, anticipated later proponents of private property among philosophers and economists, as it related to the overall utility of social arrangements.203 Aristotle believed that although communal arrangements may seem beneficial to society, and that although private property is often blamed for social strife, such evils in fact come from human nature. In Politics, Aristotle offers one of the earliest accounts of the origin of money.204 Money came into use because people became dependent on one another, importing what they needed and exporting the surplus. For the sake of convenience, people then agreed to deal in something that is intrinsically useful and easily applicable, such as iron or silver.205

Aristotle's discussions on retail and interest was a major influence on economic thought in the Middle Ages. He had a low opinion of retail, believing that contrary to using money to procure things one needs in managing the household, retail trade seeks to make a profit. It thus uses goods as a means to an end, rather than as an end unto itself. He believed that retail trade was in this way unnatural. Similarly, Aristotle considered making a profit through interest unnatural, as it makes a gain out of the money itself, and not from its use.206

Aristotle gave a summary of the function of money that was perhaps remarkably precocious for his time. He wrote that because it is impossible to determine the value of every good through a count of the number of other goods it is worth, the necessity arises of a single universal standard of measurement. Money thus allows for the association of different goods and makes them "commensurable".207 He goes on to state that money is also useful for future exchange, making it a sort of security. That is, "if we do not want a thing now, we shall be able to get it when we do want it".208

Rhetoric

Main article: Rhetoric (Aristotle)

Aristotle's Rhetoric proposes that a speaker can use three basic kinds of appeals to persuade his audience: ethos (an appeal to the speaker's character), pathos (an appeal to the audience's emotion), and logos (an appeal to logical reasoning).209 He also categorizes rhetoric into three genres: epideictic (ceremonial speeches dealing with praise or blame), forensic (judicial speeches over guilt or innocence), and deliberative (speeches calling on an audience to decide on an issue).210 Aristotle also outlines two kinds of rhetorical proofs: enthymeme (proof by syllogism) and paradeigma (proof by example).211

Poetics

Main article: Poetics (Aristotle)

Aristotle writes in his Poetics that epic poetry, tragedy, comedy, dithyrambic poetry, painting, sculpture, music, and dance are all fundamentally acts of mimesis ("imitation"), each varying in imitation by medium, object, and manner.212213 He applies the term mimesis both as a property of a work of art and also as the product of the artist's intention214 and contends that the audience's realisation of the mimesis is vital to understanding the work itself.215 Aristotle states that mimesis is a natural instinct of humanity that separates humans from animals216217 and that all human artistry "follows the pattern of nature".218 Because of this, Aristotle believed that each of the mimetic arts possesses what Stephen Halliwell calls "highly structured procedures for the achievement of their purposes."219 For example, music imitates with the media of rhythm and harmony, whereas dance imitates with rhythm alone, and poetry with language. The forms also differ in their object of imitation. Comedy, for instance, is a dramatic imitation of men worse than average; whereas tragedy imitates men slightly better than average. Lastly, the forms differ in their manner of imitation – through narrative or character, through change or no change, and through drama or no drama.220

While it is believed that Aristotle's Poetics originally comprised two books – one on comedy and one on tragedy – only the portion that focuses on tragedy has survived. Aristotle taught that tragedy is composed of six elements: plot-structure, character, style, thought, spectacle, and lyric poetry.221 The characters in a tragedy are merely a means of driving the story; and the plot, not the characters, is the chief focus of tragedy. Tragedy is the imitation of action arousing pity and fear, and is meant to effect the catharsis of those same emotions. Aristotle concludes Poetics with a discussion on which, if either, is superior: epic or tragic mimesis. He suggests that because tragedy possesses all the attributes of an epic, possibly possesses additional attributes such as spectacle and music, is more unified, and achieves the aim of its mimesis in shorter scope, it can be considered superior to epic.222 Aristotle was a keen systematic collector of riddles, folklore, and proverbs; he and his school had a special interest in the riddles of the Delphic Oracle and studied the fables of Aesop.223

Legacy

Further information: List of writers influenced by Aristotle

More than 2300 years after his death, Aristotle remains one of the most influential people who ever lived.224225226 He contributed to almost every field of human knowledge then in existence, and he was the founder of many new fields. According to the philosopher Bryan Magee, "it is doubtful whether any human being has ever known as much as he did".227 Aristotle has been regarded as the first scientist.228229

Aristotle was the founder of term logic, pioneered the study of zoology, and benefited future scientists and philosophers through his contributions to the scientific method.230231232 Taneli Kukkonen, observes that his achievement in founding two sciences is unmatched, and his reach in influencing "every branch of intellectual enterprise" including Western ethical and political theory, theology, rhetoric, and literary analysis is equally long. As a result, Kukkonen argues, any analysis of reality today "will almost certainly carry Aristotelian overtones ... evidence of an exceptionally forceful mind."233 Jonathan Barnes wrote that "an account of Aristotle's intellectual afterlife would be little less than a history of European thought".234

Aristotle has been called the father of logic, biology, political science, zoology, embryology, natural law, scientific method, rhetoric, psychology, realism, criticism, individualism, teleology, and meteorology.235

The scholar Taneli Kukkonen writes that "in the best 20th-century scholarship Aristotle comes alive as a thinker wrestling with the full weight of the Greek philosophical tradition."236 What follows is an overview of the transmission and influence of his texts and ideas into the modern era.237238

Ancient

Hellenistic period

Further information: Peripatetic school and Alexandria School of Medicine

The immediate influence of Aristotle's work was felt as the Lyceum grew into the Peripatetic school. Aristotle's students included Aristoxenus, Dicaearchus, Demetrius of Phalerum, Eudemos of Rhodes, Harpalus, Hephaestion, Mnason of Phocis, Nicomachus, and Theophrastus.239

Aristotle's pupil and successor, Theophrastus, wrote the History of Plants, a pioneering work in botany. Some of his technical terms remain in use, such as carpel from carpos, fruit, and pericarp, from pericarpion, seed chamber.240 Theophrastus was much less concerned with formal causes than Aristotle was, instead pragmatically describing how plants functioned.241242

Under the Ptolemies, the first medical teacher at Alexandria, Herophilus of Chalcedon, corrected Aristotle, placing intelligence in the brain, and connected the nervous system to motion and sensation. Herophilus also distinguished between veins and arteries, noting that the latter pulse while the former do not.243

Early Roman empire

See also: Commentaries on Aristotle

In antiquity, Aristotle's writings were divisible into two groups; the "exoteric" works, intended for the public, and the "esoteric" treatises, for use within the Lyceum school.244245 However, all of the works of Aristotle that have survived from antiquity through medieval manuscript transmission are the technical philosophical treatises from within Aristotle's school,246 which were compiled in the 1st century BC by Andronicus of Rhodes out of a series of smaller, separate works into the more cohesive, larger works as they are known today.247248

The primary way that ancient philosophers in the Roman empire engaged with Aristotle's technical work was via philosophical commentary; interpretation and explication of the text of Aristotle along with their own synthesis and views on the topics discussed by Aristotle. The peripatetic commentary tradition began with Boethus of Sidon in the 1st century BC and reached its peak at the end of the 2nd century AD with Alexander of Aphrodisias, who was appointed to the official Imperial chair of Aristotelian philosophy established by Marcus Aurelius, many of whose commentaries still survive.249

Late antiquity

In the 3rd century, Neoplatonism emerged as the dominant philosophical school. The Neoplatonists saw all subsequent philosophical systems after Plato, including Aristotle's, as developments on Plato's philosophy, and sought to explain how Plato and Aristotle were in agreement, even on subjects where they appeared to disagree, and included Aristotle's logical and physical works in their school curriculum as introductory works that needed to be mastered before the study of Plato himself. This study program began with the Categories, which the Neoplatonist philosopher Porphyry of Tyre wrote an introduction to, called Isagoge, which went on to influence subsequent philosophy in late antiquity and the medieval period. Later Neoplatonists in Athens and Alexandria including Syrianus, Ammonius Hermiae, Olympiodorus the Younger and Simplicius of Cilicia wrote further commentaries on Aristotle from a Platonist perspective which are still extant, with Simplicius compiling many of the lost works of his predecessors into massive commentaries that survey the entire Neoplatonic tradition.250

With the rise of Christianity and closure of the pagan schools by the order of Justinian in 529,251 the study of Aristotle and other philosophers in the remainder of the Byzantine period was primarily from a Christian perspective. The first Byzantine Christians to comment extensively on Aristotle were Philoponus, who was a student of Ammonius, and Elias and David, students of Olympiodorus, along with Stephen of Alexandria in the early seventh century, who brought the study of Plato and Aristotle from Alexandria to Constantinople.252 John Philoponus stands out for having attempted a fundamental critique of Aristotle's views on the eternity of the world, movement, and other elements of Aristotelian thought.253 Philoponus questioned Aristotle's teaching of physics, noting its flaws and introducing the theory of impetus to explain his observations.254

Medieval

Medieval Byzantine empire

See also: Byzantine Aristotelianism

After a hiatus of several centuries, formal commentary by Eustratius and Michael of Ephesus reappeared in the late eleventh and early twelfth centuries, apparently sponsored by Anna Comnena.255 Byzantine philosophers also filled in the gaps in the commentaries that had survived down to their time; Alexander of Aphrodisias' commentary on the Metaphysics, of which only the first five books survived, was completed by Michael of Ephesus, who also wrote a commentary on the Sophistical Refutations, the only work of the Organon not to have a commentary, and Michael of Ephesus and Eustratius compiled a number of fragmentary commentaries on the Nicomachean Ethics which they supplemented with their own interpretations. Michael of Ephesus also wrote commentaries on the works of Aristotle's animal biology and the Politics, completing the series of commentaries on Aristotle's extant works.256

Medieval Islamic world

Further information: Logic in Islamic philosophy and Transmission of the Greek Classics

Aristotle's works also underwent a revival in the Abbasid Caliphate.257 Translated into Arabic, Aristotle's logic, ethics, and natural philosophy inspired early Islamic scholars.258 Aristotle is considered the most influential figure in the history of Arabic philosophy and was revered in early Islamic theology.259 Most surviving works of Aristotle,260 as well as some of the original Greek commentaries, were translated into Arabic and studied by Muslim philosophers, scientists, and scholars. Through commentaries and critical engagements, figures like Al-Kindi,261 Al-Farabi, Ibn Sina (Avicenna), and Averroes262 breathed new life into Aristotle's ideas. They harmonized his logic with Islamic theology, employed his scientific methodology to explore the natural world, and reinterpreted his ethics within the framework of Islamic morality. Islamic thinkers embraced Aristotle's rigorous methods while challenging his conclusions where they diverged from their religious beliefs,263 which later influenced Thomas Aquinas and other Western Christian scholastic philosophers. Medieval Muslim scholars described Aristotle as the "First Teacher".264 The title was later used by Western philosophers (as in Dante's poem) who were influenced by the tradition of Islamic philosophy.265

Medieval Judaism

Moses Maimonides (considered to be the foremost intellectual figure of medieval Judaism)266 adopted Aristotelianism from the Islamic scholars and based his Guide for the Perplexed on it and that became the basis of Jewish scholastic philosophy. Maimonides also considered Aristotle to be the greatest philosopher that ever lived, and styled him as the "chief of the philosophers".267268269 Also, in his letter to Samuel ibn Tibbon, Maimonides observes that there is no need for Samuel to study the writings of philosophers who preceded Aristotle because the works of the latter are "sufficient by themselves and [superior] to all that were written before them. His intellect, Aristotle's is the extreme limit of human intellect, apart from him upon whom the divine emanation has flowed forth to such an extent that they reach the level of prophecy, there being no level higher".270

Medieval Western Europe

Further information: Aristotelianism and Syllogism § Medieval

With the loss of the study of ancient Greek in the early medieval Latin West, Aristotle was practically unknown there from c. CE 600 to c. 1100 except through the Latin translation of the Organon made by Boethius. In the twelfth and thirteenth centuries, interest in Aristotle revived and Latin Christians had translations made, both from Arabic translations, such as those by Gerard of Cremona,271 and from the original Greek, such as those by James of Venice272 and William of Moerbeke.273

After the scholastic Thomas Aquinas wrote his Summa Theologica, working from Moerbeke's translations and calling Aristotle "The Philosopher",274 the demand for Aristotle's writings grew, and the Greek manuscripts returned to the West, stimulating a revival of Aristotelianism in Europe that continued into the Renaissance.275 These thinkers blended Aristotelian philosophy with Christianity, bringing the thought of Ancient Greece into the Middle Ages. Scholars such as Boethius, Peter Abelard, and John Buridan worked on Aristotelian logic.276

According to scholar Roger Theodore Lafferty, Dante built up the philosophy of the Comedy on a foundation of Aristotle, just as the scholastics used Aristotle as the basis for their thinking. Dante knew Aristotle directly from Latin translations of his works and indirectly through quotations in the works of Albert Magnus.277 Dante acknowledges Aristotle's influence explicitly in the poem, when Virgil justifies the Inferno's structure by citing the Nicomachean Ethics.278 Dante refers to him as "he / Who is acknowledged Master of those who know".279280

Modern era

Early Modern science

In the early modern period, scientists such as William Harvey in England and Galileo Galilei in Italy reacted against the theories of Aristotle and other classical era thinkers like Galen, establishing new theories based to some degree on observation and experiment. Harvey demonstrated the circulation of the blood, establishing that the heart functioned as a pump rather than being the seat of the soul and the controller of the body's heat, as Aristotle thought.281 Galileo used more doubtful arguments to displace Aristotle's physics, proposing that bodies all fall at the same speed whatever their weight.282

18th and 19th-century science

The English mathematician George Boole fully accepted Aristotle's logic, but decided "to go under, over, and beyond" it with his system of algebraic logic in his 1854 book The Laws of Thought. This gives logic a mathematical foundation with equations, enables it to solve equations as well as check validity, and allows it to handle a wider class of problems by expanding propositions of any number of terms, not just two.283

Charles Darwin regarded Aristotle as the most important contributor to the subject of biology. In an 1882 letter he wrote that "Linnaeus and Cuvier have been my two gods, though in very different ways, but they were mere schoolboys to old Aristotle".284285 Also, in later editions of the book "On the Origin of Species', Darwin traced evolutionary ideas as far back as Aristotle;286 the text he cites is a summary by Aristotle of the ideas of the earlier Greek philosopher Empedocles.287

Present science

The philosopher Bertrand Russell claims that "almost every serious intellectual advance has had to begin with an attack on some Aristotelian doctrine". Russell calls Aristotle's ethics "repulsive", and labelled his logic "as definitely antiquated as Ptolemaic astronomy". Russell states that these errors make it difficult to do historical justice to Aristotle, until one remembers what an advance he made upon all of his predecessors.288

The Dutch historian of science Eduard Jan Dijksterhuis writes that Aristotle and his predecessors showed the difficulty of science by "proceed[ing] so readily to frame a theory of such a general character" on limited evidence from their senses.289 In 1985, the biologist Peter Medawar could still state in "pure seventeenth century"290 tones that Aristotle had assembled "a strange and generally speaking rather tiresome farrago of hearsay, imperfect observation, wishful thinking and credulity amounting to downright gullibility".291292

Zoologists have frequently mocked Aristotle for errors and unverified secondhand reports. However, modern observation has confirmed several of his more surprising claims.293294295 Aristotle's work remains largely unknown to modern scientists, though zoologists sometimes mention him as the father of biology296 or in particular of marine biology.297 Practising zoologists are unlikely to adhere to Aristotle's chain of being, but its influence is still perceptible in the use of the terms "lower" and "upper" to designate taxa such as groups of plants.298 The evolutionary biologist Armand Marie Leroi has reconstructed Aristotle's biology,299 while Niko Tinbergen's four questions, based on Aristotle's four causes, are used to analyse animal behaviour; they examine function, phylogeny, mechanism, and ontogeny.300301 The concept of homology began with Aristotle;302 the evolutionary developmental biologist Lewis I. Held commented that he would be interested in the concept of deep homology.303 In systematics too, recent studies suggest that Aristotle made important contributions in taxonomy and biological nomenclature.304305306

Depictions in art

Paintings

Aristotle has been depicted by major artists including Lucas Cranach the Elder,307 Justus van Gent, Raphael, Paolo Veronese, Jusepe de Ribera,308 Rembrandt,309 and Francesco Hayez over the centuries. Among the best-known depictions is Raphael's fresco The School of Athens, in the Vatican's Apostolic Palace, where the figures of Plato and Aristotle are central to the image, at the architectural vanishing point, reflecting their importance.310 Rembrandt's Aristotle with a Bust of Homer, too, is a celebrated work, showing the knowing philosopher and the blind Homer from an earlier age: as the art critic Jonathan Jones writes, "this painting will remain one of the greatest and most mysterious in the world, ensnaring us in its musty, glowing, pitch-black, terrible knowledge of time."311312

Sculptures

Eponyms

The Aristotle Mountains in Antarctica are named after Aristotle. He was the first person known to conjecture, in his book Meteorology, the existence of a landmass in the southern high-latitude region, which he called Antarctica.313 Aristoteles is a crater on the Moon bearing the classical form of Aristotle's name.314 (6123) Aristoteles, an asteroid in the main asteroid belt is also bearing the classical form of his name.315

See also

Notes

Citations

Sources

Further reading

The secondary literature on Aristotle is vast. The following is only a small selection.

  • Ackrill, J. L. (1997). Essays on Plato and Aristotle, Oxford University Press.
  • Ackrill, J. L. (1981). Aristotle the Philosopher. Oxford University Press.
  • Adler, Mortimer J. (1978). Aristotle for Everybody. Macmillan.
  • Ammonius (1991). Cohen, S. Marc; Matthews, Gareth B. (eds.). On Aristotle's Categories. Cornell University Press. ISBN 978-0-8014-2688-9.
  • Aristotle (1908–1952). The Works of Aristotle Translated into English Under the Editorship of W. D. Ross, 12 vols. Clarendon Press. These translations are available in several places online; see External links.
  • Bakalis, Nikolaos. (2005). Handbook of Greek Philosophy: From Thales to the Stoics Analysis and Fragments, Trafford Publishing, ISBN 978-1-4120-4843-9.
  • Bocheński, I. M. (1951). Ancient Formal Logic. North-Holland.
  • Bolotin, David (1998). An Approach to Aristotle's Physics: With Particular Attention to the Role of His Manner of Writing. Albany: SUNY Press. A contribution to our understanding of how to read Aristotle's scientific works.
  • Burnyeat, Myles F. et al. (1979). Notes on Book Zeta of Aristotle's Metaphysics. Oxford: Sub-faculty of Philosophy.
  • Cantor, Norman F.; Klein, Peter L., eds. (1969). Ancient Thought: Plato and Aristotle. Monuments of Western Thought. Vol. 1. Blaisdell.
  • Chappell, V. (1973). "Aristotle's Conception of Matter". Journal of Philosophy. 70 (19): 679–696. doi:10.2307/2025076. JSTOR 2025076.
  • Code, Alan (1995). Potentiality in Aristotle's Science and Metaphysics, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 76.
  • Cohen, S. Marc; Reeve, C. D. C. (21 November 2020). "Aristotle's Metaphysics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2020 ed.).
  • Ferguson, John (1972). Aristotle. Twayne Publishers. ISBN 978-0-8057-2064-8.
  • De Groot, Jean (2014). Aristotle's Empiricism: Experience and Mechanics in the 4th century BC, Parmenides Publishing, ISBN 978-1-930972-83-4.
  • Frede, Michael (1987). Essays in Ancient Philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
  • Fuller, B. A. G. (1923). Aristotle. History of Greek Philosophy. Vol. 3. Cape.
  • Gendlin, Eugene T. (2012). Line by Line Commentary on Aristotle's De Anima Archived 27 March 2017 at the Wayback Machine, Volume 1: Books I & II; Volume 2: Book III. The Focusing Institute.
  • Gill, Mary Louise (1989). Aristotle on Substance: The Paradox of Unity. Princeton University Press.
  • Guthrie, W. K. C. (1981). A History of Greek Philosophy. Vol. 6. Cambridge University Press.
  • Halper, Edward C. (2009). One and Many in Aristotle's Metaphysics, Volume 1: Books Alpha – Delta. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-21-6.
  • Halper, Edward C. (2005). One and Many in Aristotle's Metaphysics, Volume 2: The Central Books. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-05-6.
  • Irwin, Terence H. (1988). Aristotle's First Principles (PDF). Oxford: Clarendon Press. ISBN 0-19-824290-5.
  • Jaeger, Werner (1948). Robinson, Richard (ed.). Aristotle: Fundamentals of the History of His Development (2nd ed.). Clarendon Press.
  • Jori, Alberto (2003). Aristotele, Bruno Mondadori (Prize 2003 of the "International Academy of the History of Science"), ISBN 978-88-424-9737-0.
  • Kiernan, Thomas P., ed. (1962). Aristotle Dictionary. Philosophical Library.
  • Knight, Kelvin (2007). Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre, Polity Press.
  • Lewis, Frank A. (1991). Substance and Predication in Aristotle. Cambridge University Press.
  • Lord, Carnes (1984). Introduction to The Politics, by Aristotle. Chicago University Press.
  • Loux, Michael J. (1991). Primary Ousia: An Essay on Aristotle's Metaphysics Ζ and Η. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • Maso, Stefano (Ed.), Natali, Carlo (Ed.), Seel, Gerhard (Ed.) (2012) Reading Aristotle: Physics VII. 3: What is Alteration? Proceedings of the International ESAP-HYELE Conference, Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-73-5.
  • McKeon, Richard (1973). Introduction to Aristotle (2nd ed.). University of Chicago Press.
  • Owen, G. E. L. (1965c). "The Platonism of Aristotle". Proceedings of the British Academy. 50: 125–150. [Reprinted in J. Barnes, M. Schofield, and R. R. K. Sorabji, eds.(1975). Articles on Aristotle Vol 1. Science. London: Duckworth 14–34.]
  • Pangle, Lorraine Smith (2002). Aristotle and the Philosophy of Friendship. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511498282. ISBN 978-0-511-49828-2.
  • Plato (1979). Allen, Harold Joseph; Wilbur, James B. (eds.). The Worlds of Plato and Aristotle. Prometheus Books.
  • Roreitner, Robert (2025). Aristotle on the Nature and Causes of Perception. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9781009533829.
  • Rose, Lynn E. (1968). Aristotle's Syllogistic. Charles C. Thomas.
  • Ross, David (1995). Aristotle (6th ed.). Routledge.
  • Scaltsas, T. (1994). Substances and Universals in Aristotle's Metaphysics. Cornell University Press.
  • Strauss, Leo (1964). "On Aristotle's Politics", in The City and Man, Rand McNally.
  • Swanson, Judith (1992). The Public and the Private in Aristotle's Political Philosophy. Cornell University Press. ISBN 978-0-8014-2319-2.
  • Veatch, Henry B. (1974). Aristotle: A Contemporary Appreciation. Indiana University Press.
  • Woods, M. J. (1991b). "Universals and Particular Forms in Aristotle's Metaphysics". Aristotle and the Later Tradition. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy. Vol. Suppl. pp. 41–56.
Greek Wikisource has original works by or about:Ἀριστοτέλης Collections of works

References

  1. /ˈærɪstɒtəl/ ⓘ ARR-ih-stot-əl[1] /wiki/Help:IPA/English

  2. pronounced [aristotélɛːs] /wiki/Help:IPA/Greek

  3. See Shields 2012, pp. 3–16. Blits 1999, p. 58 writes that most information about Aristotle's life derives from Diogenes Laertius' Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers, which in turn borrows material from earlier, now mostly lost, sources. Düring 1957 covers ancient biographies of Aristotle. - Shields, Christopher (2012). The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-518748-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=vTVsrl0mnH4C

  4. That these dates (the first half of the Olympiad year 384/383 BC, and in 322 shortly before the death of Demosthenes) are correct was shown by August Boeckh (Kleine Schriften VI 195); for further discussion, see Felix Jacoby on FGrHist 244 F 38. Ingemar Düring, Aristotle in the Ancient Biographical Tradition, Göteborg, 1957, p. 253 /wiki/August_Boeckh

  5. Anagnostopoulos 2013, p. 3; Shields 2012, p. 3; Blits 1999, p. 58; Aristotle (Greek philosopher) - Anagnostopoulos, Georgios (2013). A Companion to Aristotle. Wiley. ISBN 978-1-118-59243-4.

  6. McLeisch 1999, p. 5; Hazel 2013, p. 36 - McLeisch, Kenneth Cole (1999). Aristotle: The Great Philosophers. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-92392-7. https://archive.org/details/aristotle00mcle

  7. Aristoteles-Park in Stagira. - "Aristoteles-Park in Stagira". Dimos Aristoteli. Retrieved 20 March 2018. http://www.dimosaristoteli.gr/en/sights/aristotle-park

  8. Ogden 2024, p. 32; Anagnostopoulos 2013, p. 3; Shields 2012, p. 5; Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73; Hazel 2013, p. 36; Nawotka 2009, p. 40 - Ogden, Daniel (2024). The Cambridge Companion to Alexander the Great. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-108-84099-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=LyDkEAAAQBAJ

  9. Anagnostopoulos 2013, pp. 4; Shields 2012, p. 5; Hazel 2013, pp. 36–37; Reeve & Miller 2015, p. 250 - Anagnostopoulos, Georgios (2013). A Companion to Aristotle. Wiley. ISBN 978-1-118-59243-4.

  10. Anagnostopoulos 2013, pp. 4–5; Shields 2012, p. 5; Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73; Lloyd, Brunschwig & Pellegrin 2000, p. 554 - Anagnostopoulos, Georgios (2013). A Companion to Aristotle. Wiley. ISBN 978-1-118-59243-4.

  11. Lloyd, Brunschwig & Pellegrin 2000, pp. 554–555; Hall 2018, p. 40 - Lloyd, E. R. G.; Brunschwig, Jacques; Pellegrin, Pierre (2000). Greek Thought, A Guide to Classical Knowledge. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-00261-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=kAFUjmNoQNEC

  12. Hall 2018, p. 14; Anagnostopoulos 2013, p. 4; Shields 2012, p. 5 - Hall, Edith (2018). Aristotle's Way: How Ancient Wisdom Can Change Your Life. The Bodley Head. ISBN 978-1-84792-407-0.

  13. Anagnostopoulos 2013, p. 4; Hazel 2013, p. 37; Shields 2012, p. 5 - Anagnostopoulos, Georgios (2013). A Companion to Aristotle. Wiley. ISBN 978-1-118-59243-4.

  14. Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73; Blits 1999, p. 58 - Nussbaum, Martha C.; Osborne, Catherine (2014). "Aristotle". In Hornblower, Simon; Spawforth, Antony; Eidinow, Esther (eds.). The Oxford Companion to Classical Civilization (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954556-8.

  15. Hazel 2013, p. 37. - Hazel, John (2013) [1999]. Who's Who in the Greek World. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-134-80223-4. https://books.google.com/books?id=46ay-fpRVCkC

  16. Evans 2006, p. 18. - Evans, Nancy (2006). "Diotima and Demeter as Mystagogues in Plato's Symposium". Hypatia. 21 (2): 1–27. doi:10.1111/j.1527-2001.2006.tb01091.x. ISSN 1527-2001. S2CID 143750010. https://doi.org/10.1111%2Fj.1527-2001.2006.tb01091.x

  17. Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73; Hazel 2013, p. 37 - Nussbaum, Martha C.; Osborne, Catherine (2014). "Aristotle". In Hornblower, Simon; Spawforth, Antony; Eidinow, Esther (eds.). The Oxford Companion to Classical Civilization (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954556-8.

  18. Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73. - Nussbaum, Martha C.; Osborne, Catherine (2014). "Aristotle". In Hornblower, Simon; Spawforth, Antony; Eidinow, Esther (eds.). The Oxford Companion to Classical Civilization (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954556-8.

  19. Aristotle 1984, pp. Introduction. - Aristotle (1984). Lord, Carnes (ed.). The Politics. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-92184-6. https://archive.org/details/politics0000aris

  20. Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73 write that Hermias died in 345 BC; Hazel 2013, p. 37 places Hermias' death in 342 BC, the same year as Aristotle's trip back to Macedon, while Nawotka 2009, p. 40 mentions that Hermias got arrested in 341 BC. - Nussbaum, Martha C.; Osborne, Catherine (2014). "Aristotle". In Hornblower, Simon; Spawforth, Antony; Eidinow, Esther (eds.). The Oxford Companion to Classical Civilization (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954556-8.

  21. Shields 2012, p. 6; Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73; Hazel 2013, p. 37 - Shields, Christopher (2012). The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-518748-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=vTVsrl0mnH4C

  22. Shields 2012, p. 6. - Shields, Christopher (2012). The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-518748-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=vTVsrl0mnH4C

  23. Wu 2022, p. 71; Worthington 2014b, pp. 69–70; Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73; Shields 2012, pp. 6–7; Nawotka 2009, p. 39; Green 1991, p. 54 - Wu, Yuchen (2022). "The Relationship Between Aristotle and Alexander the Great". Proceedings of the 2021 International Conference on Public Art and Human Development (ICPAHD 2021). Vol. 638. Paris, France: Atlantis Press. doi:10.2991/assehr.k.220110.015. ISBN 978-94-6239-523-7. ISSN 2352-5398. https://doi.org/10.2991%2Fassehr.k.220110.015

  24. Ogden 2024, p. 32; Shields 2012, p. 5; Nawotka 2009, pp. 39–40; Lloyd, Brunschwig & Pellegrin 2000, p. 555 - Ogden, Daniel (2024). The Cambridge Companion to Alexander the Great. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-108-84099-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=LyDkEAAAQBAJ

  25. Ogden 2024, p. 32; Worthington 2014a, p. 34; Shields 2012, p. 7; Nawotka 2009, p. 39 - Ogden, Daniel (2024). The Cambridge Companion to Alexander the Great. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-108-84099-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=LyDkEAAAQBAJ

  26. Wu 2022, p. 71; Nawotka 2009, p. 40 - Wu, Yuchen (2022). "The Relationship Between Aristotle and Alexander the Great". Proceedings of the 2021 International Conference on Public Art and Human Development (ICPAHD 2021). Vol. 638. Paris, France: Atlantis Press. doi:10.2991/assehr.k.220110.015. ISBN 978-94-6239-523-7. ISSN 2352-5398. https://doi.org/10.2991%2Fassehr.k.220110.015

  27. Hornblower 2002, p. 91; Hazel 2013, p. 37 - Hornblower, Simon (2002). The Greek World, 479–323 BC. Routledge. ISBN 0-415-16326-9.

  28. Worthington 2014a, pp. 34–35; Nawotka 2009, pp. 41–42; Green 1991, pp. 58–59 - Worthington, Ian (2014a) [2004]. Alexander the Great: Man and God. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-86644-2. https://books.google.com/books?id=xnQABAAAQBAJ

  29. Green 1991, pp. 58–59; Worthington 2014b, p. 96 - Green, Peter (1991). Alexander of Macedon. University of California Press. ISBN 978-0-520-27586-7. https://archive.org/details/alexanderofmaced0000gree

  30. Worthington 2014b, p. 97; Hazel 2013, p. 37 - Worthington, Ian (2014b). By the Spear: Philip II, Alexander the Great, and the Rise and Fall of the Macedonian Empire. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-992986-3. https://books.google.com/books?id=vnGVAwAAQBAJ

  31. Ogden 2024, p. 32; Worthington 2014b, pp. 97, 186; Nawotka 2009, p. 40 - Ogden, Daniel (2024). The Cambridge Companion to Alexander the Great. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-108-84099-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=LyDkEAAAQBAJ

  32. Ogden 2024, p. 32; Hazel 2013, p. 37 provides the alternative translations On Monarchy and Colonists - Ogden, Daniel (2024). The Cambridge Companion to Alexander the Great. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-108-84099-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=LyDkEAAAQBAJ

  33. Shields 2012, p. 7. - Shields, Christopher (2012). The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-518748-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=vTVsrl0mnH4C

  34. Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73; Hazel 2013, p. 37; Shields 2012, p. 7 - Nussbaum, Martha C.; Osborne, Catherine (2014). "Aristotle". In Hornblower, Simon; Spawforth, Antony; Eidinow, Esther (eds.). The Oxford Companion to Classical Civilization (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954556-8.

  35. Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73; Hazel 2013, p. 37 - Nussbaum, Martha C.; Osborne, Catherine (2014). "Aristotle". In Hornblower, Simon; Spawforth, Antony; Eidinow, Esther (eds.). The Oxford Companion to Classical Civilization (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954556-8.

  36. Shields 2012, p. 7; Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73; Hazel 2013, p. 37 - Shields, Christopher (2012). The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-518748-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=vTVsrl0mnH4C

  37. Shields 2012, p. 7; Hazel 2013, p. 37 - Shields, Christopher (2012). The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-518748-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=vTVsrl0mnH4C

  38. Shields 2012, p. 7; Russell 1972 - Shields, Christopher (2012). The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-518748-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=vTVsrl0mnH4C

  39. Humphreys 2009. - Humphreys, Justin (2009). "Aristotle (384–322 B.C.E.)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/aristotl

  40. Wu 2022, pp. 72–74. - Wu, Yuchen (2022). "The Relationship Between Aristotle and Alexander the Great". Proceedings of the 2021 International Conference on Public Art and Human Development (ICPAHD 2021). Vol. 638. Paris, France: Atlantis Press. doi:10.2991/assehr.k.220110.015. ISBN 978-94-6239-523-7. ISSN 2352-5398. https://doi.org/10.2991%2Fassehr.k.220110.015

  41. Green 1991, p. 460. - Green, Peter (1991). Alexander of Macedon. University of California Press. ISBN 978-0-520-27586-7. https://archive.org/details/alexanderofmaced0000gree

  42. Filonik 2013, pp. 72–73. - Filonik, Jakub (2013). "Athenian impiety trials: a reappraisal". Dike. 16 (16): 72–73. doi:10.13130/1128-8221/4290. https://doi.org/10.13130%2F1128-8221%2F4290

  43. Jones 1980, p. 216; Gigon 2017, p. 41; Düring 1957, p. T44a-e - Jones, W. T. (1980). The Classical Mind: A History of Western Philosophy. Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. ISBN 978-0-15-538312-8.

  44. Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73. - Nussbaum, Martha C.; Osborne, Catherine (2014). "Aristotle". In Hornblower, Simon; Spawforth, Antony; Eidinow, Esther (eds.). The Oxford Companion to Classical Civilization (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954556-8.

  45. Aristotle (Greek philosopher). - "Aristotle (Greek philosopher)". Encyclopædia Britannica. Britannica Online Encyclopedia. Archived from the original on 22 April 2009. Retrieved 26 April 2009. https://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/34560/Aristotle

  46. Britton, Bianca (27 May 2016). "Is this Aristotle's tomb?". CNN. Retrieved 21 January 2023. https://www.cnn.com/2016/05/27/europe/greece-aristotle-tomb/index.html

  47. Haase 1992, p. 3862. - Haase, Wolfgang (1992). Philosophie, Wissenschaften, Technik. Philosophie (Doxographica [Forts. ]) (in German). Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-013699-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=ifqGuiHo6eQC&pg=PA3862

  48. Hazel 2013, p. 38; Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73 - Hazel, John (2013) [1999]. Who's Who in the Greek World. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-134-80223-4. https://books.google.com/books?id=46ay-fpRVCkC

  49. Degnan 1994, pp. 81–89. - Degnan, Michael (1994). "Recent Work in Aristotle's Logic". Philosophical Books. 35 (2 (April 1994)): 81–89. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0149.1994.tb02858.x. https://doi.org/10.1111%2Fj.1468-0149.1994.tb02858.x

  50. Corcoran 2009, pp. 1–20. - Corcoran, John (2009). "Aristotle's Demonstrative Logic". History and Philosophy of Logic. 30: 1–20. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.650.463. doi:10.1080/01445340802228362. S2CID 8514675. https://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/summary?doi=10.1.1.650.463

  51. Kant 1787, pp. Preface. - Kant, Immanuel (1787). Critique of Pure Reason (Second ed.). OCLC 2323615. https://search.worldcat.org/oclc/2323615

  52. Pickover 2009, p. 52. - Pickover, Clifford A. (2009). The Math Book: From Pythagoras to the 57th Dimension, 250 Milestones in the History of Mathematics. Sterling. ISBN 978-1-4027-5796-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=JrslMKTgSZwC&pg=PA52

  53. Prior Analytics, pp. 24b18–20. - Aristotle. "Prior Analytics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/prior.html

  54. Bobzien 2015. - Bobzien, Susanne (2015). "Ancient Logic". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University – via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/logic-ancient/

  55. Smith 2017. - Smith, Robin (2017). "Aristotle's Logic". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-logic/

  56. This type of syllogism, with all three terms in 'a', is known by the traditional (medieval) mnemonic Barbara.[53] /wiki/Syllogism#Types

  57. M is the Middle (here, Men), S is the Subject (Greeks), P is the Predicate (mortal).[53]

  58. The first equation can be read as 'It is not true that there exists an x such that x is a man and that x is not mortal.'[54]

  59. Lagerlund 2016. - Lagerlund, Henrik (2016). "Medieval Theories of the Syllogism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/medieval-syllogism/

  60. Evans, John David Gemmill (1977). Aristotle's concept of dialectic. Cambridge University Press. pp. 86–87.

  61. Duncombe, Matthew; Dutilh Novaes, Catarina (2 January 2016). "Dialectic and logic in Aristotle and his tradition" (PDF). History and Philosophy of Logic. 37 (1): 1–8. doi:10.1080/01445340.2015.1086624. ISSN 0144-5340. https://pure.rug.nl/ws/portalfiles/portal/80567692/Dialectic_and_logic_in_Aristotle_and_his_tradition.pdf

  62. Smith 2017. - Smith, Robin (2017). "Aristotle's Logic". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-logic/

  63. Smith 2017. - Smith, Robin (2017). "Aristotle's Logic". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-logic/

  64. Cohen 2000. - Cohen, S. Marc (8 October 2000). "Aristotle's Metaphysics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.). Retrieved 14 November 2018. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/aristotle-metaphysics/

  65. Cohen 2000. - Cohen, S. Marc (8 October 2000). "Aristotle's Metaphysics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.). Retrieved 14 November 2018. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/aristotle-metaphysics/

  66. Aristotle 1999, p. 111. - Aristotle (1999). Aristotle's Metaphysics. Translated by Sachs, Joe. Green Lion Press.

  67. Metaphysics, pp. VIII 1043a 10–30. - Aristotle. "Metaphysics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/metaphysics.html

  68. Cohen 2000. - Cohen, S. Marc (8 October 2000). "Aristotle's Metaphysics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.). Retrieved 14 November 2018. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/aristotle-metaphysics/

  69. Cohen 2000. - Cohen, S. Marc (8 October 2000). "Aristotle's Metaphysics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.). Retrieved 14 November 2018. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/aristotle-metaphysics/

  70. Cohen 2000. - Cohen, S. Marc (8 October 2000). "Aristotle's Metaphysics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.). Retrieved 14 November 2018. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/aristotle-metaphysics/

  71. Lloyd 1968, pp. 43–47. - Lloyd, G. E. R. (1968). "Aristotle: The Growth and Structure of His Thought". The critic of Plato. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-09456-6.

  72. Cohen 2000. - Cohen, S. Marc (8 October 2000). "Aristotle's Metaphysics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.). Retrieved 14 November 2018. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/aristotle-metaphysics/

  73. Metaphysics, p. IX 1050a 5–10. - Aristotle. "Metaphysics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/metaphysics.html

  74. Cohen 2000. - Cohen, S. Marc (8 October 2000). "Aristotle's Metaphysics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.). Retrieved 14 November 2018. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/aristotle-metaphysics/

  75. Metaphysics, p. VIII 1045a–b. - Aristotle. "Metaphysics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/metaphysics.html

  76. Wildberg 2016. - Wildberg (2016). "John Philoponus". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/philoponus/

  77. Wildberg 2016. - Wildberg (2016). "John Philoponus". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/philoponus/

  78. Lloyd 1968, pp. 133–139, 166–169. - Lloyd, G. E. R. (1968). "Aristotle: The Growth and Structure of His Thought". The critic of Plato. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-09456-6.

  79. Lloyd 1968, pp. 133–139, 166–169. - Lloyd, G. E. R. (1968). "Aristotle: The Growth and Structure of His Thought". The critic of Plato. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-09456-6.

  80. Allain 2016. - Allain, Rhett (21 March 2016). "I'm So Totally Over Newton's Laws of Motion". Wired. Retrieved 11 May 2018. https://www.wired.com/2016/03/im-totally-newtons-laws-motion/

  81. Rhett Allain notes that Newton's First Law is "essentially a direct reply to Aristotle, that the natural state is not to change motion.[65] /wiki/Newton%27s_First_Law

  82. Drabkin 1938, pp. 60–84. - Drabkin, Israel E. (1938). "Notes on the Laws of Motion in Aristotle". The American Journal of Philology. 59 (1): 60–84. doi:10.2307/290584. JSTOR 90584. https://doi.org/10.2307%2F290584

  83. Susskind 2011. - Susskind, Leonard (3 October 2011). "Classical Mechanics, Lectures 2, 3". The Theoretical Minimum. Retrieved 11 May 2018. http://theoreticalminimum.com/courses/classical-mechanics/2011/fall/lecture-2

  84. Leonard Susskind comments that Aristotle had clearly never gone ice skating or he would have seen that it takes force to stop an object.[67] /wiki/Ice_skating

  85. Susskind 2011. - Susskind, Leonard (3 October 2011). "Classical Mechanics, Lectures 2, 3". The Theoretical Minimum. Retrieved 11 May 2018. http://theoreticalminimum.com/courses/classical-mechanics/2011/fall/lecture-2

  86. Susskind 2011. - Susskind, Leonard (3 October 2011). "Classical Mechanics, Lectures 2, 3". The Theoretical Minimum. Retrieved 11 May 2018. http://theoreticalminimum.com/courses/classical-mechanics/2011/fall/lecture-2

  87. For heavenly bodies like the Sun, Moon, and stars, the observed motions are "to a very good approximation" circular around the Earth's centre, (for example, the apparent rotation of the sky because of the rotation of the Earth, and the rotation of the moon around the Earth) as Aristotle stated.[68]

  88. Rovelli 2015, pp. 23–40. - Rovelli, Carlo (2015). "Aristotle's Physics: A Physicist's Look". Journal of the American Philosophical Association. 1 (1): 23–40. arXiv:1312.4057. doi:10.1017/apa.2014.11. S2CID 44193681. https://arxiv.org/abs/1312.4057

  89. Drabkin 1938, pp. 60–84. - Drabkin, Israel E. (1938). "Notes on the Laws of Motion in Aristotle". The American Journal of Philology. 59 (1): 60–84. doi:10.2307/290584. JSTOR 90584. https://doi.org/10.2307%2F290584

  90. Drabkin quotes numerous passages from Physics and On the Heavens (De Caelo) which state Aristotle's laws of motion.[66]

  91. Drabkin agrees that density is treated quantitatively in this passage, but without a sharp definition of density as weight per unit volume.[66]

  92. Rovelli 2015, pp. 23–40. - Rovelli, Carlo (2015). "Aristotle's Physics: A Physicist's Look". Journal of the American Philosophical Association. 1 (1): 23–40. arXiv:1312.4057. doi:10.1017/apa.2014.11. S2CID 44193681. https://arxiv.org/abs/1312.4057

  93. Drabkin 1938, pp. 60–84. - Drabkin, Israel E. (1938). "Notes on the Laws of Motion in Aristotle". The American Journal of Philology. 59 (1): 60–84. doi:10.2307/290584. JSTOR 90584. https://doi.org/10.2307%2F290584

  94. Rovelli 2015, pp. 23–40. - Rovelli, Carlo (2015). "Aristotle's Physics: A Physicist's Look". Journal of the American Philosophical Association. 1 (1): 23–40. arXiv:1312.4057. doi:10.1017/apa.2014.11. S2CID 44193681. https://arxiv.org/abs/1312.4057

  95. Drabkin 1938, pp. 60–84. - Drabkin, Israel E. (1938). "Notes on the Laws of Motion in Aristotle". The American Journal of Philology. 59 (1): 60–84. doi:10.2307/290584. JSTOR 90584. https://doi.org/10.2307%2F290584

  96. Drabkin 1938, pp. 60–84. - Drabkin, Israel E. (1938). "Notes on the Laws of Motion in Aristotle". The American Journal of Philology. 59 (1): 60–84. doi:10.2307/290584. JSTOR 90584. https://doi.org/10.2307%2F290584

  97. Carteron 1923, pp. 1–32 and passim. - Carteron, Henri (1923). Notion de Force dans le Systeme d'Aristote (in French). J. Vrin.

  98. Drabkin 1938, pp. 60–84. - Drabkin, Israel E. (1938). "Notes on the Laws of Motion in Aristotle". The American Journal of Philology. 59 (1): 60–84. doi:10.2307/290584. JSTOR 90584. https://doi.org/10.2307%2F290584

  99. Rovelli 2015, pp. 23–40. - Rovelli, Carlo (2015). "Aristotle's Physics: A Physicist's Look". Journal of the American Philosophical Association. 1 (1): 23–40. arXiv:1312.4057. doi:10.1017/apa.2014.11. S2CID 44193681. https://arxiv.org/abs/1312.4057

  100. Wildberg 2016. - Wildberg (2016). "John Philoponus". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/philoponus/

  101. Rovelli 2015, pp. 23–40. - Rovelli, Carlo (2015). "Aristotle's Physics: A Physicist's Look". Journal of the American Philosophical Association. 1 (1): 23–40. arXiv:1312.4057. doi:10.1017/apa.2014.11. S2CID 44193681. https://arxiv.org/abs/1312.4057

  102. Susskind 2011. - Susskind, Leonard (3 October 2011). "Classical Mechanics, Lectures 2, 3". The Theoretical Minimum. Retrieved 11 May 2018. http://theoreticalminimum.com/courses/classical-mechanics/2011/fall/lecture-2

  103. Philoponus and Galileo correctly objected that for the transient phase (still increasing in speed) with heavy objects falling a short distance, the law does not apply: Galileo used balls on a short incline to show this. Rovelli notes that "Two heavy balls with the same shape and different weight do fall at different speeds from an aeroplane, confirming Aristotle's theory, not Galileo's."[68]

  104. Rovelli 2015, pp. 23–40. - Rovelli, Carlo (2015). "Aristotle's Physics: A Physicist's Look". Journal of the American Philosophical Association. 1 (1): 23–40. arXiv:1312.4057. doi:10.1017/apa.2014.11. S2CID 44193681. https://arxiv.org/abs/1312.4057

  105. Lloyd 1996, pp. 96–100, 106–107. - Lloyd, G. E. R. (1996). "Adversaries and Authorities: Investigations into ancient Greek and Chinese science". Causes and Correlations. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-55695-8.

  106. Hankinson 1998, p. 159. - Hankinson, R. J. (1998). Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0199246564.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-823745-7. https://doi.org/10.1093%2F0199246564.001.0001

  107. Lloyd 1996, pp. 96–100, 106–107. - Lloyd, G. E. R. (1996). "Adversaries and Authorities: Investigations into ancient Greek and Chinese science". Causes and Correlations. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-55695-8.

  108. Lloyd 1996, pp. 96–100, 106–107. - Lloyd, G. E. R. (1996). "Adversaries and Authorities: Investigations into ancient Greek and Chinese science". Causes and Correlations. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-55695-8.

  109. Lloyd 1996, pp. 96–100, 106–107. - Lloyd, G. E. R. (1996). "Adversaries and Authorities: Investigations into ancient Greek and Chinese science". Causes and Correlations. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-55695-8.

  110. Leroi 2015, pp. 91–92, 369–373. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  111. Lloyd 1996, pp. 96–100, 106–107. - Lloyd, G. E. R. (1996). "Adversaries and Authorities: Investigations into ancient Greek and Chinese science". Causes and Correlations. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-55695-8.

  112. Leroi 2015, pp. 91–92, 369–373. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  113. Burnyeat, Myles F. "Archytas and optics". Science in Context 18.1 (2005): pp. 35-53. https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/science-in-context/article/abs/archytas-and-optics/BDBF3868CEF7004C16547836D66A4F24

  114. Berryman, Sylvia (2012). "'It Makes No Difference': Optics and Natural Philosophy in Late Antiquity". Apeiron. 45 (3). doi:10.1515/apeiron-2012-0001. https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/apeiron-2012-0001/html

  115. Cantor, Geoffrey N. "Physical optics". Companion to the History of Modern Science. Routledge, 2006. pp. 627–638.

  116. Matthen, Mohan. "Is the eye like what it sees? A critique of Aristotle on sensing by assimilation". Vivarium 57.3-4 (2019): pp. 268–292. https://philpapers.org/archive/MATITE-3.docx

  117. Physics, p. 2.6. - Aristotle. "Physics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 31 January 2019. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/physics.html

  118. Miller 1973, pp. 204–213. - Miller, Willard M. (1973). "Aristotle on Necessity, Chance, and Spontaneity". New Scholasticism. 47 (2): 204–213. doi:10.5840/newscholas197347237. https://doi.org/10.5840%2Fnewscholas197347237

  119. Meteorology, p. 1. 8. - Aristotle. "Meteorology". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/meteorology.html

  120. Meteorology. - Aristotle. "Meteorology". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/meteorology.html

  121. Moore 1956, p. 13. - Moore, Ruth (1956). The Earth We Live On. Alfred A. Knopf. OCLC 1024467091. https://archive.org/details/earthweliveonsto00moor

  122. Meteorology, p. Book 1, Part 14. - Aristotle. "Meteorology". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/meteorology.html

  123. Lyell 1832, p. 17. - Lyell, Charles (1832). Principles of Geology. J. Murray, 1832. OCLC 609586345. https://archive.org/details/principlesgeolo01unkngoog

  124. Udias, Agustin; Buforn, Elisa (2018). Principles of Seismology. Cambridge University Press. p. 1.

  125. Aristotle (1952). Meteorologica, Chapter II. Translated by Lee, H. D. P. (Loeb Classical Library ed.). Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. p. 156. Retrieved 22 January 2021. http://archive.org/details/L397AristotleMeteorologica

  126. Leroi 2015, p. 7. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  127. Leroi 2015, p. 14. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  128. Thompson 1910, p. Prefatory Note. - Thompson, D'Arcy (1910). Ross, W. D.; Smith, J. A. (eds.). Historia animalium – The works of Aristotle translated into English. Clarendon Press. OCLC 39273217. Archived from the original on 9 August 2019. Retrieved 19 March 2018. https://web.archive.org/web/20190809140240/https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/history/index.html

  129. "Darwin's Ghosts, By Rebecca Stott". The Independent (UK). 2 June 2012. Retrieved 19 June 2012. https://www.independent.co.uk/arts-entertainment/books/reviews/darwins-ghosts-by-rebecca-stott-7808310.html

  130. Leroi 2015, pp. 196, 248. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  131. Day 2013, pp. 5805–5816. - Day, J. (2013). "Botany meets archaeology: people and plants in the past". Journal of Experimental Botany. 64 (18): 5805–5816. doi:10.1093/jxb/ert068. PMID 23669575. https://doi.org/10.1093%2Fjxb%2Fert068

  132. Leroi 2015, pp. 66–74, 137. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  133. Leroi 2015, pp. 118–119. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  134. Leroi 2015, p. 73. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  135. Leroi 2015, pp. 135–136. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  136. Leroi 2015, p. 206. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  137. Sedley 2007, p. 189. - Sedley, David (2007). Creationism and Its Critics in Antiquity. University of California Press. ISBN 978-0-520-25364-3. https://books.google.com/books?id=SgRuJEfzUG8C

  138. Leroi 2015, p. 273. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  139. Taylor 1922, p. 42. - Taylor, Henry Osborn (1922). "Chapter 3: Aristotle's Biology". Greek Biology and Medicine. Archived from the original on 27 March 2006. Retrieved 3 January 2017. https://web.archive.org/web/20060327222953/http://www.ancientlibrary.com/medicine/0051.html

  140. Leroi 2015, pp. 361–365. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  141. Leroi 2011. - Leroi, Armand Marie (3 May 2011). "Aristotle's Lagoon: Embryo Inside a Chicken's Egg". BBC. Retrieved 17 November 2016. https://www.bbc.co.uk/programmes/p00gqlyy

  142. Leroi 2015, pp. 197–200. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  143. Leroi 2015, pp. 365–368. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  144. Taylor 1922, p. 49. - Taylor, Henry Osborn (1922). "Chapter 3: Aristotle's Biology". Greek Biology and Medicine. Archived from the original on 27 March 2006. Retrieved 3 January 2017. https://web.archive.org/web/20060327222953/http://www.ancientlibrary.com/medicine/0051.html

  145. Leroi 2015, pp. 365–368. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  146. Leroi 2015, p. 408. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  147. Bergstrom & Dugatkin 2012, p. 35. - Bergstrom, Carl T.; Dugatkin, Lee Alan (2012). Evolution. Norton. ISBN 978-0-393-92592-0. https://books.google.com/books?id=SeaEZwEACAAJ

  148. Rhodes 1974, p. 7. - Rhodes, Frank Harold Trevor (1974). Evolution. Golden Press. ISBN 978-0-307-64360-5. https://books.google.com/books?id=EWGt0bff8agC

  149. Mayr 1982, pp. 201–202. - Mayr, Ernst (1982). The Growth of Biological Thought. Belknap Press. ISBN 978-0-674-36446-2. https://archive.org/details/growthofbiologic00mayr

  150. Lovejoy 1976. - Lovejoy, Arthur O. (31 January 1976). The Great Chain of Being: A Study of the History of an Idea. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-36153-9.

  151. Leroi 2015, pp. 111–119. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  152. Lennox, James G. (2001). Aristotle's Philosophy of Biology: Studies in the Origins of Life Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 346. ISBN 0-521-65976-0. 0-521-65976-0

  153. Sandford, Stella (3 December 2019). "From Aristotle to Contemporary Biological Classification: What Kind of Category is "Sex"?". Redescriptions: Political Thought, Conceptual History and Feminist Theory. 22 (1): 4–17. doi:10.33134/rds.314. ISSN 2308-0914. S2CID 210140121. https://doi.org/10.33134%2Frds.314

  154. Voultsiadou, Eleni; Gerovasileiou, Vasilis; Vandepitte, Leen; Ganias, Kostas; Arvanitidis, Christos (2017). "Aristotle's scientific contributions to the classification, nomenclature and distribution of marine organisms". Mediterranean Marine Science. 18 (3): 468–478. doi:10.12681/mms.13874. ISSN 1791-6763. https://doi.org/10.12681/mms.13874

  155. von Lieven, Alexander Fürst; Humar, Marcel (2008). "A Cladistic Analysis of Aristotle's Animal Groups in the "Historia animalium"". History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences. 30 (2): 227–262. ISSN 0391-9714. JSTOR 23334371. PMID 19203017. https://www.jstor.org/stable/23334371

  156. Laurin, Michel (3 August 2023). The Advent of PhyloCode: The Continuing Evolution of Biological Nomenclature (section 1.1.3). Boca Raton, Fl: CRC Press. pp. xv + 209. ISBN 978-1-00-091257-9. 978-1-00-091257-9

  157. Leroi 2015, pp. 156–163. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  158. Shields 2016. - Shields, Christopher (2016). "Aristotle's Psychology". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.).

  159. Mason 1979, p. 45. - Mason, Stephen F. (1979). A History of the Sciences. Collier Books. ISBN 978-0-02-093400-4. OCLC 924760574. https://books.google.com/books?id=PLlMAAAAMAAJ

  160. Guthrie 2010, p. 348. - Guthrie, W. (2010). A History of Greek Philosophy Vol. 1. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-29420-1.

  161. On the Soul, I.3 406b26-407a10. - Aristotle. "On the Soul". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/soul.html

  162. For instance, Ross, William D. ed. 1961. Aristotle: De Anima. Oxford: Oxford University Press, page 189.

  163. On the Soul, I.3 407b14–27. - Aristotle. "On the Soul". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/soul.html

  164. Bloch 2007, p. 12. - Bloch, David (2007). Aristotle on Memory and Recollection. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-16046-0. https://books.google.com/books?id=QwTHng_5RqAC&q=Aristotle+on+Memory+and+Recollection&pg=PR9

  165. Bloch 2007, p. 61. - Bloch, David (2007). Aristotle on Memory and Recollection. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-16046-0. https://books.google.com/books?id=QwTHng_5RqAC&q=Aristotle+on+Memory+and+Recollection&pg=PR9

  166. Carruthers 2007, p. 16. - Carruthers, Mary (2007). The Book of Memory: A Study of Memory in Medieval Culture. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-42973-3. https://books.google.com/books?id=dntrAnqfIasC&q=The+book+of+memory:+the+study+of+memory+in+medieval+times&pg=PR8

  167. Bloch 2007, p. 25. - Bloch, David (2007). Aristotle on Memory and Recollection. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-16046-0. https://books.google.com/books?id=QwTHng_5RqAC&q=Aristotle+on+Memory+and+Recollection&pg=PR9

  168. Warren 1921, p. 30. - Warren, Howard C. (1921). A History of the Association of Psychology. C. Scribner's sons. ISBN 978-0-598-91975-5. https://books.google.com/books?id=D4IXAAAAYAAJ&q=The+history+of+the+association+of+psychology&pg=PA3

  169. Warren 1921, p. 25. - Warren, Howard C. (1921). A History of the Association of Psychology. C. Scribner's sons. ISBN 978-0-598-91975-5. https://books.google.com/books?id=D4IXAAAAYAAJ&q=The+history+of+the+association+of+psychology&pg=PA3

  170. Carruthers 2007, p. 19. - Carruthers, Mary (2007). The Book of Memory: A Study of Memory in Medieval Culture. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-42973-3. https://books.google.com/books?id=dntrAnqfIasC&q=The+book+of+memory:+the+study+of+memory+in+medieval+times&pg=PR8

  171. Warren 1921, p. 296. - Warren, Howard C. (1921). A History of the Association of Psychology. C. Scribner's sons. ISBN 978-0-598-91975-5. https://books.google.com/books?id=D4IXAAAAYAAJ&q=The+history+of+the+association+of+psychology&pg=PA3

  172. Warren 1921, p. 259. - Warren, Howard C. (1921). A History of the Association of Psychology. C. Scribner's sons. ISBN 978-0-598-91975-5. https://books.google.com/books?id=D4IXAAAAYAAJ&q=The+history+of+the+association+of+psychology&pg=PA3

  173. Sorabji 2006, p. 54. - Sorabji, R. (2006). Aristotle on Memory (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. p. 54. And this is exactly why we hunt for the successor, starting in our thoughts from the present or from something else, and from something similar, or opposite, or neighbouring. By this means recollection occurs...

  174. Holowchak 1996, pp. 405–423. - Holowchak, Mark (1996). "Aristotle on Dreaming: What Goes on in Sleep when the 'Big Fire' goes out". Ancient Philosophy. 16 (2): 405–423. doi:10.5840/ancientphil199616244. http://www.pdcnet.org/ancientphil/Ancient-Philosophy

  175. Shute 1941, pp. 115–118. - Shute, Clarence (1941). The Psychology of Aristotle: An Analysis of the Living Being. Columbia University Press. OCLC 936606202. https://search.worldcat.org/oclc/936606202

  176. Holowchak 1996, pp. 405–23. - Holowchak, Mark (1996). "Aristotle on Dreaming: What Goes on in Sleep when the 'Big Fire' goes out". Ancient Philosophy. 16 (2): 405–423. doi:10.5840/ancientphil199616244. http://www.pdcnet.org/ancientphil/Ancient-Philosophy

  177. Shute 1941, pp. 115–118. - Shute, Clarence (1941). The Psychology of Aristotle: An Analysis of the Living Being. Columbia University Press. OCLC 936606202. https://search.worldcat.org/oclc/936606202

  178. Shute 1941, pp. 115–118. - Shute, Clarence (1941). The Psychology of Aristotle: An Analysis of the Living Being. Columbia University Press. OCLC 936606202. https://search.worldcat.org/oclc/936606202

  179. Holowchak 1996, pp. 405–423. - Holowchak, Mark (1996). "Aristotle on Dreaming: What Goes on in Sleep when the 'Big Fire' goes out". Ancient Philosophy. 16 (2): 405–423. doi:10.5840/ancientphil199616244. http://www.pdcnet.org/ancientphil/Ancient-Philosophy

  180. Shute 1941, pp. 115–118. - Shute, Clarence (1941). The Psychology of Aristotle: An Analysis of the Living Being. Columbia University Press. OCLC 936606202. https://search.worldcat.org/oclc/936606202

  181. Holowchak 1996, pp. 405–423. - Holowchak, Mark (1996). "Aristotle on Dreaming: What Goes on in Sleep when the 'Big Fire' goes out". Ancient Philosophy. 16 (2): 405–423. doi:10.5840/ancientphil199616244. http://www.pdcnet.org/ancientphil/Ancient-Philosophy

  182. Shute 1941, pp. 115–118. - Shute, Clarence (1941). The Psychology of Aristotle: An Analysis of the Living Being. Columbia University Press. OCLC 936606202. https://search.worldcat.org/oclc/936606202

  183. Holowchak 1996, pp. 405–423. - Holowchak, Mark (1996). "Aristotle on Dreaming: What Goes on in Sleep when the 'Big Fire' goes out". Ancient Philosophy. 16 (2): 405–423. doi:10.5840/ancientphil199616244. http://www.pdcnet.org/ancientphil/Ancient-Philosophy

  184. Modrak 2009, pp. 169–181. - Modrak, Deborah (2009). "Dreams and Method in Aristotle". Skepsis: A Journal for Philosophy and Interdisciplinary Research. 20: 169–181.

  185. Holowchak 1996, pp. 405–423. - Holowchak, Mark (1996). "Aristotle on Dreaming: What Goes on in Sleep when the 'Big Fire' goes out". Ancient Philosophy. 16 (2): 405–423. doi:10.5840/ancientphil199616244. http://www.pdcnet.org/ancientphil/Ancient-Philosophy

  186. Holowchak 1996, pp. 405–423. - Holowchak, Mark (1996). "Aristotle on Dreaming: What Goes on in Sleep when the 'Big Fire' goes out". Ancient Philosophy. 16 (2): 405–423. doi:10.5840/ancientphil199616244. http://www.pdcnet.org/ancientphil/Ancient-Philosophy

  187. Shields 2016. - Shields, Christopher (2016). "Aristotle's Psychology". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.).

  188. Webb 1990, pp. 174–184. - Webb, Wilse (1990). Dreamtime and dreamwork: Decoding the language of the night. Jeremy P. Tarcher. ISBN 978-0-87477-594-5. https://archive.org/details/dreamtimedreamwo00kriprich

  189. Modrak 2009, pp. 169–181. - Modrak, Deborah (2009). "Dreams and Method in Aristotle". Skepsis: A Journal for Philosophy and Interdisciplinary Research. 20: 169–181.

  190. Wildberg 2016. - Wildberg (2016). "John Philoponus". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/philoponus/

  191. Humphreys 2009. - Humphreys, Justin (2009). "Aristotle (384–322 B.C.E.)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/aristotl

  192. Kraut 2001. - Kraut, Richard (1 May 2001). "Aristotle's Ethics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 19 March 2018. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-ethics/

  193. Humphreys 2009. - Humphreys, Justin (2009). "Aristotle (384–322 B.C.E.)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/aristotl

  194. Nicomachean Ethics Book I. See for example chapter 7. - Aristotle. "Nicomachean Ethics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/nicomachaen.html

  195. Nicomachean Ethics, Book VI. - Aristotle. "Nicomachean Ethics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/nicomachaen.html

  196. Politics, pp. 1253a19–124. - Aristotle. "Politics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/politics.html

  197. Aristotle 2009, pp. 320–321. - Aristotle (2009) [1995]. Politics. Translated by Ernest Barker and revised with introduction and notes by R. F. Stalley (1st ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-953873-7.

  198. Ebenstein & Ebenstein 2002, p. 59. - Ebenstein, Alan; Ebenstein, William (2002). Introduction to Political Thinkers. Wadsworth Group.

  199. For a different reading of social and economic processes in the Nicomachean Ethics and Politics see Polanyi, Karl (1957) "Aristotle Discovers the Economy" in Primitive, Archaic and Modern Economies: Essays of Karl Polanyi ed. G. Dalton, Boston 1971, 78–115.

  200. Hutchinson & Johnson 2015, p. 22. - Hutchinson, D. S.; Johnson, Monte Ransome (2015). "Exhortation to Philosophy" (PDF). Protrepticus. p. 22. http://www.protrepticus.info/protr2017x20.pdf

  201. Hutchinson & Johnson 2015, p. 22. - Hutchinson, D. S.; Johnson, Monte Ransome (2015). "Exhortation to Philosophy" (PDF). Protrepticus. p. 22. http://www.protrepticus.info/protr2017x20.pdf

  202. Robbins 2000, pp. 20–24. - Robbins, Lionel (2000). Medema, Steven G.; Samuels, Warren J. (eds.). A History of Economic Thought: The LSE Lectures. Princeton University Press.

  203. Robbins 2000, pp. 20–24. - Robbins, Lionel (2000). Medema, Steven G.; Samuels, Warren J. (eds.). A History of Economic Thought: The LSE Lectures. Princeton University Press.

  204. Robbins 2000, pp. 20–24. - Robbins, Lionel (2000). Medema, Steven G.; Samuels, Warren J. (eds.). A History of Economic Thought: The LSE Lectures. Princeton University Press.

  205. Aristotle 1948, pp. 16–28. - Aristotle (1948). Monroe, Arthur E. (ed.). Politics-Ethics, In Early Economic Thought: Selections from Economic Literature Prior to Adam Smith. Harvard University Press.

  206. Aristotle 1948, pp. 16–28. - Aristotle (1948). Monroe, Arthur E. (ed.). Politics-Ethics, In Early Economic Thought: Selections from Economic Literature Prior to Adam Smith. Harvard University Press.

  207. Aristotle 1948, pp. 16–28. - Aristotle (1948). Monroe, Arthur E. (ed.). Politics-Ethics, In Early Economic Thought: Selections from Economic Literature Prior to Adam Smith. Harvard University Press.

  208. Aristotle 1948, pp. 16–28. - Aristotle (1948). Monroe, Arthur E. (ed.). Politics-Ethics, In Early Economic Thought: Selections from Economic Literature Prior to Adam Smith. Harvard University Press.

  209. Garver 1994, pp. 109–110. - Garver, Eugene (1994). Aristotle's Rhetoric: An Art of Character. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-28425-5. https://books.google.com/books?id=J2ldWwIQhHwC&q=Aristotle+ethos+pathos+logos

  210. Rorty 1996, pp. 3–7. - Rorty, Amélie Oksenberg (1996). "Structuring Rhetoric". In Rorty, Amélie Oksenberg (ed.). Essays on Aristotle's Rhetoric. University of California Press. ISBN 978-0-520-20227-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=vd7fEb1wOmYC&q=Aristotle+deliberative+forensic+and+epideictic&pg=PA6

  211. Grimaldi 1998, p. 71. - Grimaldi, William M. A. (1998). "Studies in the Philosophy of Aristotle's Rhetoric". In Enos, Richard Leo; Agnew, Lois Peters (eds.). Landmark Essays on Aristotelian Rhetoric. Vol. 14. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. p. 71. ISBN 978-1-880393-32-1. https://books.google.com/books?id=sMihW5GdDzoC&q=Aristotle+paradeigma+and+enthymeme&pg=PA71

  212. Halliwell 2002, pp. 152–159. - Halliwell, Stephen (2002). "Inside and Outside the Work of Art". The Aesthetics of Mimesis: Ancient Texts and Modern Problems. Princeton University Press. pp. 152–59. ISBN 978-0-691-09258-4. https://books.google.com/books?id=R8wctGFg12MC&q=Aristotle+mimesis

  213. Poetics, p. I 1447a. - Aristotle. "Poetics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/poetics.html

  214. Halliwell 2002, pp. 152–159. - Halliwell, Stephen (2002). "Inside and Outside the Work of Art". The Aesthetics of Mimesis: Ancient Texts and Modern Problems. Princeton University Press. pp. 152–59. ISBN 978-0-691-09258-4. https://books.google.com/books?id=R8wctGFg12MC&q=Aristotle+mimesis

  215. Halliwell 2002, pp. 152–159. - Halliwell, Stephen (2002). "Inside and Outside the Work of Art". The Aesthetics of Mimesis: Ancient Texts and Modern Problems. Princeton University Press. pp. 152–59. ISBN 978-0-691-09258-4. https://books.google.com/books?id=R8wctGFg12MC&q=Aristotle+mimesis

  216. Halliwell 2002, pp. 152–159. - Halliwell, Stephen (2002). "Inside and Outside the Work of Art". The Aesthetics of Mimesis: Ancient Texts and Modern Problems. Princeton University Press. pp. 152–59. ISBN 978-0-691-09258-4. https://books.google.com/books?id=R8wctGFg12MC&q=Aristotle+mimesis

  217. Poetics, p. IV. - Aristotle. "Poetics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/poetics.html

  218. Halliwell 2002, pp. 152–159. - Halliwell, Stephen (2002). "Inside and Outside the Work of Art". The Aesthetics of Mimesis: Ancient Texts and Modern Problems. Princeton University Press. pp. 152–59. ISBN 978-0-691-09258-4. https://books.google.com/books?id=R8wctGFg12MC&q=Aristotle+mimesis

  219. Halliwell 2002, pp. 152–59. - Halliwell, Stephen (2002). "Inside and Outside the Work of Art". The Aesthetics of Mimesis: Ancient Texts and Modern Problems. Princeton University Press. pp. 152–59. ISBN 978-0-691-09258-4. https://books.google.com/books?id=R8wctGFg12MC&q=Aristotle+mimesis

  220. Poetics, p. III. - Aristotle. "Poetics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/poetics.html

  221. Poetics, p. VI. - Aristotle. "Poetics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/poetics.html

  222. Poetics, p. XXVI. - Aristotle. "Poetics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/poetics.html

  223. Aesop 1998, pp. Introduction, xi–xii. - Aesop (1998). The Complete Fables By Aesop. Translated by Temple, Olivia; Temple, Robert. Penguin Classics. ISBN 978-0-14-044649-4. https://books.google.com/books?id=ZB-rVxPvtPEC&pg=PR3

  224. Leroi 2015, p. 8. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  225. Aristotle's Influence 2018. - Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Aristotle's Influence". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018 ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-influence/

  226. Garner., Dwight (14 March 2014). "Who's More Famous Than Jesus?". The New York Times. Archived from the original on 1 April 2021. https://web.archive.org/web/20210401095825/https://www.nytimes.com/2014/03/16/magazine/whos-more-famous-than-jesus.html

  227. Magee 2010, p. 34. - Magee, Bryan (2010). The Story of Philosophy. Dorling Kindersley. ISBN 978-0-241-24126-4.

  228. Kullmann, Wolfgang (1991). "Aristotle as a Natural Scientist". Acta Classica. 34: 137–150. ISSN 0065-1141. JSTOR 24591937. https://www.jstor.org/stable/24591937

  229. Lo Presti, Roberto (21 August 2014). "History of science: The first scientist". Nature (journal). 512 (7514): 250–251. Bibcode:2014Natur.512..250L. doi:10.1038/512250a. ISSN 0028-0836. https://www.nature.com/articles/512250a

  230. Aristotle (Greek philosopher). - "Aristotle (Greek philosopher)". Encyclopædia Britannica. Britannica Online Encyclopedia. Archived from the original on 22 April 2009. Retrieved 26 April 2009. https://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/34560/Aristotle

  231. Durant 2006, p. 92. - Durant, Will (2006) [1926]. The Story of Philosophy. Simon & Schuster. ISBN 978-0-671-73916-4.

  232. Kukkonen 2010, pp. 70–77. - Kukkonen, Taneli (2010). Grafton, Anthony; et al. (eds.). The classical tradition. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-03572-0.

  233. Kukkonen 2010, pp. 70–77. - Kukkonen, Taneli (2010). Grafton, Anthony; et al. (eds.). The classical tradition. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-03572-0.

  234. Barnes 1982, p. 86. - Barnes, Jonathan (1982). Aristotle: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-285408-7.

  235. * "the father of logic": Wentzel Van Huyssteen, Encyclopedia of Science and Religion: A–I, p. 27 "the father of biology": S. C. Datt, S. B. Srivastava, Science and society, p. 93.[170] "the father of political science": N. Jayapalan, Aristotle, p. 12, Jonathan Wolff, Lectures on the History of Moral and Political Philosophy, p. 48. the "father of zoology": Josef Rudolf Winkler, A Book of Beetles, p. 12 "the father of embryology": D. R. Khanna, Text Book Of Embryology, p. 2 "the father of natural law": Shellens, Max Solomon (1959). "Aristotle on Natural Law". Natural Law Forum. 4 (1): 72–100. doi:10.1093/ajj/4.1.72. ISSN 0065-8995. "the father of scientific method": Shuttleworth, Martyn. "History of the Scientific Method". Explorable., Riccardo Pozzo (2004) The impact of Aristotelianism on modern philosophy. CUA Press. p. 41. ISBN 0-8132-1347-9 "the father of psychology": Margot Esther Borden, Psychology in the Light of the East, p. 4 "the father of realism": Russell L. Hamm, Philosophy and Education: Alternatives in Theory and Practice, p. 58 "the father of criticism": Nagendra Prasad, Personal Bias in Literary Criticism: Johnson, Matthew Arnold, T. S. Eliot, p. 70. Lord Henry Home Kames, Elements of Criticism, p. 237. "the father of meteorology":"What is meteorology?". Meteorological Office."94.05.01: Meteorology". Archived from the original on 21 July 2016. Retrieved 16 June 2015. "the father of individualism": Allan Gotthelf, Gregory Salmieri, A Companion to Ayn Rand, p. 325. "the father of teleology": Malcolm Owen Slavin, Daniel H. Kriegman, The Adaptive Design of the Human Psyche: Psychoanalysis, Evolutionary Biology, and the Therapeutic Process, p. 292.

  236. Kukkonen 2010, pp. 70–77. - Kukkonen, Taneli (2010). Grafton, Anthony; et al. (eds.). The classical tradition. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-03572-0.

  237. Russell 1972, Chapter 19 "Aristotle's Metaphysics". - Russell, Bertrand (1972). A history of western philosophy. Simon and Schuster. ISBN 978-0-671-31400-2. https://books.google.com/books?id=RZc3AAAAIAAJ

  238. Wilkins 2009, p. 15. - Wilkins, John (2009). Species: a history of the idea. Berkeley: University of California Press. p. 15. ISBN 978-0-520-27139-5. OCLC 314379168. https://search.worldcat.org/oclc/314379168

  239. Ostwald & Lynch 1982, pp. 623–624. - Ostwald, M.; Lynch, J. (1982). "The Growth of Schools & the Advance of Knowledge". In Lewis, D. M.; Boardman, John; Hornblower, Simon; et al. (eds.). The Cambridge Ancient History Volume 6: The Fourth Century BCE. Cambridge University Press.

  240. Hooker 1831, p. 219. - Hooker, William Jackson (1831). The British Flora: Comprising the Phaenogamous, Or Flowering Plants, and the Ferns. Longman. OCLC 17317293. https://books.google.com/books?id=v-IYAAAAYAAJ&pg=PA219

  241. Mayr 1982, pp. 90–91. - Mayr, Ernst (1982). The Growth of Biological Thought. Belknap Press. ISBN 978-0-674-36446-2. https://archive.org/details/growthofbiologic00mayr

  242. Mason 1979, p. 46. - Mason, Stephen F. (1979). A History of the Sciences. Collier Books. ISBN 978-0-02-093400-4. OCLC 924760574. https://books.google.com/books?id=PLlMAAAAMAAJ

  243. Mason 1979, p. 56. - Mason, Stephen F. (1979). A History of the Sciences. Collier Books. ISBN 978-0-02-093400-4. OCLC 924760574. https://books.google.com/books?id=PLlMAAAAMAAJ

  244. Barnes 1995, p. 12. - Barnes, Jonathan (1995). "Life and Work". The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-42294-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=WBqQOqM5dfsC

  245. House 1956, p. 35. - House, Humphry (1956). Aristotle's Poetics. Rupert Hart-Davis. https://archive.org/details/aristotlespoetic032945mbp

  246. Barnes 1995, p. 9. - Barnes, Jonathan (1995). "Life and Work". The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-42294-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=WBqQOqM5dfsC

  247. Anagnostopoulos 2013, p. 16. - Anagnostopoulos, Georgios (2013). A Companion to Aristotle. Wiley. ISBN 978-1-118-59243-4.

  248. Barnes 1995, pp. 10–15. - Barnes, Jonathan (1995). "Life and Work". The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-42294-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=WBqQOqM5dfsC

  249. Falcon 2021.

  250. Falcon 2021.

  251. Ahbel-Rappe 2010, p. 424 (note 17), Notes to Pages 4-7. - Damascius' Problems and Solutions Concerning First Principles (in English and Ancient Greek). Translated by Ahbel-Rappe, Sara. New York: Oxford University Press, Inc. 2010. ISBN 9780195150292.

  252. Sorabji 1990. - Sorabji, Richard (1990). Aristotle Transformed. Duckworth. ISBN 978-0-7156-2254-4.

  253. Sorabji 1990, pp. 233–724. - Sorabji, Richard (1990). Aristotle Transformed. Duckworth. ISBN 978-0-7156-2254-4.

  254. Lindberg 1992, p. 162. - Lindberg, David (1992). The Beginnings of Western Science. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-48205-7. https://archive.org/details/beginningsofwest00lind

  255. Sorabji 1990, pp. 20–21, 28–29, 393–406, 407–408. - Sorabji, Richard (1990). Aristotle Transformed. Duckworth. ISBN 978-0-7156-2254-4.

  256. Ierodiakonou 2008.

  257. Gutas, Dimitri (1998). The Graeco-Arabic Translation Movement in Baghdad and Early 'Abbasaid Society (1stglish ed.). Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-415-06133-9. 978-0-415-06133-9

  258. Admin (13 February 2017). "The Reception of Aristotelian Science in Early Islam: A Historical Account". Interdisciplinary Humanities Center UCSB. Retrieved 27 January 2024. https://www.ihc.ucsb.edu/reception-of-aristotelian-science/

  259. Alwishah, Ahmed; Hayes, Josh (2015). Aristotle and the Arabic Tradition. Cambridge University Press. p. 1. ISBN 978-1-107-10173-9. 978-1-107-10173-9

  260. Kennedy-Day 1998. - Kennedy-Day, Kiki (1998). "Aristotelianism in Islamic philosophy". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Taylor and Francis. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-H002-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. https://doi.org/10.4324%2F9780415249126-H002-1

  261. Staley 1989. - Staley, Kevin (1989). "Al-Kindi on Creation: Aristotle's Challenge to Islam". Journal of the History of Ideas. 50 (3): 355–370. doi:10.2307/2709566. JSTOR 2709566. https://doi.org/10.2307%2F2709566

  262. Averroes 1953, p. III, 2, 43. - Averroes (1953). Crawford, F. Stuart (ed.). Commentarium Magnum in Aristotelis De Anima Libros. Mediaeval Academy of America. OCLC 611422373. https://search.worldcat.org/oclc/611422373

  263. Fakhry, Majid (1987). A History of Islamic Philosophy (2nd ed.). Columbia University Press. ISBN 978-0-231-05533-8. 978-0-231-05533-8

  264. Kennedy-Day 1998. - Kennedy-Day, Kiki (1998). "Aristotelianism in Islamic philosophy". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Taylor and Francis. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-H002-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. https://doi.org/10.4324%2F9780415249126-H002-1

  265. Nasr 1996, pp. 59–60. - Nasr, Seyyed Hossein (1996). The Islamic Intellectual Tradition in Persia. Curzon Press. ISBN 978-0-7007-0314-2.

  266. "Moses Maimonides". Britannica. 26 March 2023. https://www.britannica.com/biography/Moses-Maimonides

  267. Levi ben Gershom, The Wars of the Lord: Book one, Immortality of the soul, p. 35.

  268. Leon Simon, Aspects Of The Hebrew Genius: A Volume Of Essays On Jewish Literature And Thought (1910), p. 127.

  269. Herbert A. Davidson, Herbert A. |q (Herbert Alan) Davidson, Professor of Hebrew Emeritus Herbert Davidson, Moses Maimonides: The Man and His Works, p. 98.

  270. Menachem Kellner, Maimonides on Judaism and the Jewish People, p. 77.

  271. Hasse 2014. - Hasse, Dag Nikolaus (2014). "Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the Latin West". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-influence/

  272. "Medieval Chronology" (PDF). bc.edu. Archived from the original (PDF) on 17 September 2006. Retrieved 8 March 2007. https://web.archive.org/web/20060917002914/http://www2.bc.edu/~solere/docs/medieval_chronology.pdf

  273. "Aristutalis" in Encyclopedia of Islam 2nd. ed. Brill, Leiden, Vol. 1 p. 631.

  274. Aquinas 2013. - Aquinas, Thomas (2013). Summa Theologica. e-artnow. ISBN 978-80-7484-292-4. https://books.google.com/books?id=YiJCBAAAQBAJ

  275. Kuhn 2018. - Kuhn, Heinrich (2018). "Aristotelianism in the Renaissance". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotelianism-renaissance/

  276. Lagerlund 2016. - Lagerlund, Henrik (2016). "Medieval Theories of the Syllogism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/medieval-syllogism/

  277. Lafferty, Roger. "The Philosophy of Dante", p. 4 https://www.jstor.org/stable/pdf/40165857.pdf?refreqid=excelsior%3A55f6bfc22f02768d5dcdc92005228933

  278. Inferno, Canto XI, lines 70–115, Mandelbaum translation.

  279. Inferno, Canto IV, lines 115-16 trans., 131 original, Robert Pinksky translation (1994); note to line, p.384

  280. Kukkonen 2010, p. 74. - Kukkonen, Taneli (2010). Grafton, Anthony; et al. (eds.). The classical tradition. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-03572-0.

  281. Aird 2011, pp. 118–29. - Aird, W. C. (2011). "Discovery of the cardiovascular system: from Galen to William Harvey". Journal of Thrombosis and Haemostasis. 9: 118–129. doi:10.1111/j.1538-7836.2011.04312.x. PMID 21781247. S2CID 12092592. https://doi.org/10.1111%2Fj.1538-7836.2011.04312.x

  282. Machamer 2017. - Machamer, Peter (2017). "Galileo Galilei". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/galileo/

  283. Boole 2003. - Boole, George (2003) [1854]. The Laws of Thought. Prometheus Books. ISBN 978-1-59102-089-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=nUEQAQAAIAAJ

  284. Wilkins, John (2009). Species: a history of the idea. Berkeley: University of California Press. p. 15. ISBN 978-0-520-27139-5. OCLC 314379168. 978-0-520-27139-5

  285. Pasipoularides, Ares (2010). The heart's vortex: intracardiac blood flow phenomena. Shelton, Connecticut: People's Medical Publishing House. p. 118. ISBN 978-1-60795-033-2. OCLC 680621287. 978-1-60795-033-2

  286. Darwin 1872, p. xiii - Darwin, Charles (1872). The Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life (6th ed.). London: John Murray. Retrieved 9 January 2009. http://darwin-online.org.uk/content/frameset?itemID=F391&viewtype=text&pageseq=1

  287. Aristotle. "Physics". translated by Hardie, R. P. and Gayle, R. K. and hosted by MIT's Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 23 April 2009. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/physics.2.ii.html

  288. Russell 1972, Chapter 19 "Aristotle's Metaphysics". - Russell, Bertrand (1972). A history of western philosophy. Simon and Schuster. ISBN 978-0-671-31400-2. https://books.google.com/books?id=RZc3AAAAIAAJ

  289. Dijksterhuis 1969, p. 72. - Dijksterhuis, Eduard Jan (1969). The Mechanization of the World Picture. Translated by C. Dikshoorn. Princeton University Press.

  290. Leroi 2015, p. 353. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  291. Leroi 2015, p. 353. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  292. Medawar & Medawar 1984, p. 28. - Medawar, Peter B.; Medawar, J. S. (1984). Aristotle to Zoos: a philosophical dictionary of biology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-283043-2.

  293. Ogilvie, Brian W. (2010). "Zoology". In Grafton, Anthony; Most, Glenn W.; Settis, Salvatore (eds.). The Classical Tradition. Harvard University Press. pp. 1000–1001. ISBN 978-0-674-07227-5. 978-0-674-07227-5

  294. Forbes, Peter (2009). Dazzled and Deceived: Mimicry and Camouflage. Yale University Press. pp. 236–239. ISBN 978-0-300-12539-9. 978-0-300-12539-9

  295. Leroi 2015, pp. 137–138. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  296. Leroi 2015, p. 352. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  297. "A History of the Study of Marine Biology". MarineBio Conservation Society. Retrieved 19 November 2016. http://marinebio.org/oceans/history-of-marine-biology/

  298. Rigato, Emanuele; Minelli, Alessandro (28 June 2013). "The great chain of being is still here". Evolution: Education and Outreach. 6 (18): 1–6. doi:10.1186/1936-6434-6-18. ISSN 1936-6434. http://www.evolution-outreach.com/content/6/1/18

  299. Leroi 2015. - Leroi, Armand Marie (2015). The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.

  300. MacDougall-Shackleton 2011, pp. 2076–2085. - MacDougall-Shackleton, Scott A. (27 July 2011). "The levels of analysis revisited". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 366 (1574): 2076–2085. doi:10.1098/rstb.2010.0363. PMC 3130367. PMID 21690126. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3130367

  301. Hladký & Havlíček 2013. - Hladký, V.; Havlíček, J. (2013). "Was Tinbergen an Aristotelian? Comparison of Tinbergen's Four Whys and Aristotle's Four Causes" (PDF). Human Ethology Bulletin. 28 (4): 3–11. http://ishe.org/wp-content/uploads/2015/04/HEB_2013_28_4_3-11.pdf

  302. Panchen, A. L. (1999). "Homology—History of a Concept". Novartis Foundation Symposium 222 – Homology. Novartis Foundation Symposia. Vol. 222. pp. 5–18, discussion 18–23. doi:10.1002/9780470515655.ch2. ISBN 978-0-470-51565-5. PMID 10332750. 978-0-470-51565-5

  303. Held, Lewis I. (February 2017). Deep Homology?: Uncanny Similarities of Humans and Flies Uncovered by Evo-Devo. Cambridge University Press. p. viii. ISBN 978-1-316-60121-1. 978-1-316-60121-1

  304. Voultsiadou, Eleni; Vafidis, Dimitris (1 January 2007). "Marine invertebrate diversity in Aristotle's zoology". Contributions to Zoology. 76 (2): 103–120. doi:10.1163/18759866-07602004. ISSN 1875-9866. S2CID 55152069. https://doi.org/10.1163/18759866-07602004

  305. Ganias, Kostas; Mezarli, Charikleia; Voultsiadou, Eleni (November 2017). "Aristotle as an ichthyologist: Exploring Aegean fish diversity 2,400 years ago". Fish and Fisheries. 18 (6): 1038–1055. Bibcode:2017AqFF...18.1038G. doi:10.1111/faf.12223. ISSN 1467-2960. https://doi.org/10.1111/faf.12223

  306. Laurin, Michel; Humar, Marcel (2022). "Phylogenetic signal in characters from Aristotle's History of Animals". Comptes Rendus Palevol (in French). 21 (1): 1–16. doi:10.5852/cr-palevol2022v21a1. S2CID 245863171. https://doi.org/10.5852%2Fcr-palevol2022v21a1

  307. Lucas Cranach the Elder. - "Lucas Cranach the Elder| Phyllis and Aristotle". Sotheby's. 2008. Retrieved 23 March 2018. http://www.sothebys.com/en/auctions/ecatalogue/2008/important-old-master-paintings-including-european-works-of-art-n08404/lot.78.html

  308. Lee & Robinson 2005. - Lee, Ellen Wardwell; Robinson, Anne (2005). Indianapolis Museum of Art: Highlights of the Collection. Indianapolis Museum of Art. ISBN 978-0-936260-77-8.

  309. Aristotle with Bust 2002. - "Aristotle with a Bust of Homer, Rembrandt (1653)". The Guardian. 27 July 2002. Retrieved 23 March 2018. https://www.theguardian.com/culture/2002/jul/27/art.homer

  310. Phelan 2002. - Phelan, Joseph (September 2002). "The Philosopher as Hero: Raphael's The School of Athens". ArtCyclopedia. Retrieved 23 March 2018. http://www.artcyclopedia.com/feature-2002-09.html

  311. Held 1969. - Held, Julius (1969). Rembrandt's Aristotle and Other Rembrandt Studies. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-03862-9. https://archive.org/details/rembrandtsaristo0000held

  312. Jones 2002. - Jones, Jonathan (27 July 2002). "Aristotle with a Bust of Homer, Rembrandt (1653)". The Guardian. Retrieved 23 March 2018. https://www.theguardian.com/culture/2002/jul/27/art.homer

  313. Aristotle Mountains. - "Aristotle Mountains". SCAR Composite Antarctic Gazetteer. Programma Nazionale di Ricerche in Antartide. Department of the Environment and Energy, Australian Antarctic Division, Australian Government. Retrieved 1 March 2018. https://data.aad.gov.au/aadc/gaz/scar/display_name.cfm?gaz_id=137410

  314. Aristoteles. - "Aristoteles". Gazetteer of Planetary Nomenclature. United States Geological Survey. Retrieved 19 March 2018. https://planetarynames.wr.usgs.gov/nomenclature/SearchResults;jsessionid=BE8F9834B709207DDD5D36EFA5506C7F

  315. "IAU Minor Planet Center". minorplanetcenter.net. Retrieved 1 July 2024. https://minorplanetcenter.net/db_search/show_object?object_id=6123