Main article: Fair division of a single homogeneous resource
Suppose society has m {\displaystyle m} units of some homogeneous divisible resource, such as water or flour. The resource should be divided among n {\displaystyle n} agents with different utilities. The utility of agent i {\displaystyle i} is represented by a function u i {\displaystyle u_{i}} ; when agent i {\displaystyle i} receives y i {\displaystyle y_{i}} units of resource, he derives from it a utility of u i ( y i ) {\displaystyle u_{i}(y_{i})} . Society has to decide how to divide the resource among the agents, i.e, to find a vector y 1 , … , y n {\displaystyle y_{1},\dots ,y_{n}} such that: y 1 + ⋯ + y n = m {\displaystyle y_{1}+\cdots +y_{n}=m} .
Two classic allocation rules are the egalitarian rule - aiming to equalize the utilities of all agents (equivalently: maximize the minimum utility), and the utilitarian rule - aiming to maximize the sum of utilities.
The egalitarian rule is always RM:3: 47 when there is more resource to share, the minimum utility that can be guaranteed to all agents increases, and all agents equally share the increase. In contrast, the utilitarian rule might be not RM.
For example, suppose there are two agents, Alice and Bob, with the following utilities:
The egalitarian allocation is found by solving the equation: y A 2 = ( m − y A ) {\displaystyle y_{A}^{2}=(m-y_{A})} , which is equivalent to m = y A 2 + y A {\displaystyle m=y_{A}^{2}+y_{A}} , so y A {\displaystyle y_{A}} is monotonically increasing with m {\displaystyle m} . An equivalent equation is: y B = ( m − y B ) 2 {\displaystyle y_{B}=(m-y_{B})^{2}} , which is equivalent to m = y B + y B {\displaystyle m={\sqrt {y_{B}}}+y_{B}} , so y B {\displaystyle y_{B}} too is monotonically increasing with m {\displaystyle m} . So in this example (as always) the egalitarian rule is RM.
In contrast, the utilitarian rule is not RM. This is because Alice has increasing returns: her marginal utility is small when she has few resources, but it increases fast when she has many resources. Hence, when the total amount of resource is small (specifically, m < 1 {\displaystyle m<1} ), the utilitarian sum is maximized when all resources are given to Bob; but when there are many resources ( m > 1 {\displaystyle m>1} ), the maximum is attained when all resources are given to Alice. Mathematically, if y {\displaystyle y} is the amount given to Alice, then the utilitarian sum is y 2 + ( m − y ) {\displaystyle y^{2}+(m-y)} . This function has only an internal minimum point but not an internal maximum point; its maximum point in the range [ 0 , m ] {\displaystyle [0,m]} is attained in one of the endpoints. It is the left endpoint when m < 1 {\displaystyle m<1} and the right endpoint when m > 1 {\displaystyle m>1} . In general, the utilitarian allocation rule is RM when all agents have diminishing returns, but it may be not RM when some agents have increasing returns (as in the example).4: 46–47
Thus, if society uses the utilitarian rule to allocate resources, then Bob loses value when the amount of resources increases. This is bad because it gives Bob an incentive against economic growth: Bob will try to keep the total amount small in order to keep his own share large.
Consider a cloud server with some units of RAM and CPU. There are two users with different types of tasks:
Thus, the utility functions (=number of tasks), denoting RAM by r and CPU by c, are Leontief utilities:
If the server has 12 RAM and 12 CPU, then both the utilitarian and the egalitarian allocations (and also the Nash-optimal, max-product allocation) are:
Now, suppose 12 more units of CPU become available. The egalitarian allocation does not change, but the utilitarian allocation now gives all resources to Alice:
so Bob loses value from the increase in resources.
The Nash-optimal (max-product) allocation becomes:
so Bob loses value here too, but the loss is less severe.5: 83–84
In the fair cake-cutting problem, classic allocation rules such as divide and choose are not RM. Several rules are known to be RM:
Resource-monotonicity was studied in problems of fair division with single-peaked preferences.89
The egalitarian rule (maximizing the leximin vector of utilities) might be not RM when the resource to divide consists of several indivisible (discrete) units.
For example,10: 82 suppose there are m {\displaystyle m} tennis rackets. Alice gets a utility of 1 whenever she has a racket, since she enjoys playing against the wall. But Bob and Carl get a utility of 1 only when they have two rackets, since they only enjoy playing against each other or against Alice. Hence, if there is only one racket, the egalitarian rule gives it entirely to Alice. But if there are two rackets, they are divided equally between the agents (each agent gets a racket for 2/3 of the time). Hence, Alice loses utility when the total amount of rackets increases. Alice has an incentive to oppose growth.
In the fair item allocation problem, classic allocation procedures such as adjusted winner and envy-graph are not RM. Moreover, even the Nash-optimal rule, which is RM in cake-cutting, is not RM in item allocation. In contrast, round-robin item allocation is RM. Moreover, round-robin can be adapted to yield picking sequences appropriate for agents with different entitlements; all these picking sequences are RM too.11
Main article: House monotonicity
The special case in which all items are identical and each agent's utility is simply the number of items he receives is known as apportionment. It originated from the task of allocating seats in a parliament among states or among parties. Therefore, it is often called house monotonicity.
Facility location is the social choice question is where a certain facility should be located. Consider the following network of roads, where the letters denote junctions and the numbers denote distances:
A---6---B--5--C--5--D---6---E
The population is distributed uniformly along the roads. People want to be as close as possible to the facility, so they have "dis-utility" (negative utility) measured by their distance to the facility.
In the initial situation, the egalitarian rule locates the facility at C, since it minimizes the maximum distance to the facility, which is 11 (the utilitarian and Nash rules also locate the facility at C).
Now, there is a new junction X and some new roads (the previous roads do not change):
The egalitarian rule now locates the facility at X, since it allows to decrease the maximum distance from 11 to 9 (the utilitarian and Nash rules also locate the facility at X).
The increase in resources helped most people, but decreased the utility of those living in or near C.12: 84–85
A monotonicity axiom closely related to resource-monotonicity appeared first in the context of the bargaining problem. A bargaining problem is defined by a set of alternatives; a bargaining solution should select a single alternative from the set, subject to some axioms. The resource-monotonicity axiom was presented in two variants:
14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21
Herve Moulin (2004). Fair Division and Collective Welfare. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. ISBN 9780262134231. 9780262134231 ↩
Thomson, William (2011). Fair Allocation Rules. Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare. Vol. 2. pp. 393–506. doi:10.1016/s0169-7218(10)00021-3. ISBN 9780444508942. 9780444508942 ↩
Segal-Halevi, Erel; Sziklai, Balázs R. (2019-09-01). "Monotonicity and competitive equilibrium in cake-cutting". Economic Theory. 68 (2): 363–401. arXiv:1510.05229. doi:10.1007/s00199-018-1128-6. ISSN 1432-0479. S2CID 179618. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-018-1128-6 ↩
Segal-Halevi, Erel; Sziklai, Balázs R. (2018-09-01). "Resource-monotonicity and population-monotonicity in connected cake-cutting". Mathematical Social Sciences. 95: 19–30. arXiv:1703.08928. doi:10.1016/j.mathsocsci.2018.07.001. ISSN 0165-4896. S2CID 16282641. http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0165489618300520 ↩
Thomson, William (1994). "Resource-monotonic solutions to the problem of fair division when preferences are single-peaked". Social Choice and Welfare. 11 (3). doi:10.1007/bf00193807. S2CID 122306487. /wiki/Doi_(identifier) ↩
Thomson, William (1997). "The Replacement Principle in Economies with Single-Peaked Preferences". Journal of Economic Theory. 76: 145–168. doi:10.1006/jeth.1997.2294. https://doi.org/10.1006%2Fjeth.1997.2294 ↩
Chakraborty, Mithun; Schmidt-Kraepelin, Ulrike; Suksompong, Warut (2021-04-29). "Picking sequences and monotonicity in weighted fair division". Artificial Intelligence. 301: 103578. arXiv:2104.14347. doi:10.1016/j.artint.2021.103578. S2CID 233443832. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier) ↩
Kalai, Ehud (1977). "Proportional solutions to bargaining situations: Intertemporal utility comparisons" (PDF). Econometrica. 45 (7): 1623–1630. doi:10.2307/1913954. JSTOR 1913954. http://www.kellogg.northwestern.edu/research/math/papers/179.pdf ↩
Mantel, Rolf R. (1984). "Substitutability and the welfare effects of endowment increases". Journal of International Economics. 17 (3–4): 325–334. doi:10.1016/0022-1996(84)90027-8. /wiki/Doi_(identifier) ↩
Moulin, Hervé (1992). "Welfare bounds in the cooperative production problem". Games and Economic Behavior. 4 (3): 373–401. doi:10.1016/0899-8256(92)90045-t. /wiki/Doi_(identifier) ↩
Polterovich, V.M.; Spivak, V.A. (1983). "Gross substitutability of point-to-set correspondences". Journal of Mathematical Economics. 11 (2): 117. doi:10.1016/0304-4068(83)90032-0. /wiki/Doi_(identifier) ↩
Sobel, Joel (1979). "Fair allocations of a renewable resource". Journal of Economic Theory. 21 (2): 235–248. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.394.9698. doi:10.1016/0022-0531(79)90029-2. /wiki/CiteSeerX_(identifier) ↩
Moulin, Hervé; Thomson, William (1988). "Can everyone benefit from growth?". Journal of Mathematical Economics. 17 (4): 339. doi:10.1016/0304-4068(88)90016-x. /wiki/Doi_(identifier) ↩
Moulin, Herve (1992). "An Application of the Shapley Value to Fair Division with Money". Econometrica. 60 (6): 1331–1349. doi:10.2307/2951524. JSTOR 2951524. /wiki/Doi_(identifier) ↩
Moulin, H. (1990). "Fair division under joint ownership: Recent results and open problems". Social Choice and Welfare. 7 (2): 149–170. doi:10.1007/bf01560582. S2CID 154300207. /wiki/Doi_(identifier) ↩
Moulin, Hervé (1991). "Welfare bounds in the fair division problem". Journal of Economic Theory. 54 (2): 321–337. doi:10.1016/0022-0531(91)90125-n. /wiki/Doi_(identifier) ↩